Skip to main content
Log in

Moral Innocence as Illusion and Inability

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The concept of moral innocence is frequently referenced in popular culture, ordinary language, literature, religious doctrine, and psychology. The morally innocent are often thought to be morally pure, incapable of wrongdoing, ignorant of morality, resistant to sin, or even saintly. In spite of, or perhaps because of this frequency of use the characterization of moral innocence continues to have varying connotations. As a result, the concept is often used without sufficient heed given to some of its most salient attributes, especially those germane to moral agency and the moral community. In this article I intend to identify these attributes and propose that moral innocence is best defined as an inability to enter the moral community as a result of a trust in moral illusions. The content of the illusions pertains to several factors including one’s role(s) in the moral community, one’s ability to wrong or harm others, the intricacies of one’s moral interaction with others, and the corresponding manifold complexities tangled up with the concepts of good and evil. Maintaining these illusions impedes or even prohibits an appropriate exchange of praise and blame with others. As membership in the moral community requires precisely this ability to engage in such an exchange, moral illusions necessarily give rise to an inability to participate in the moral community.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example: See Blake (1789); Wordsworth (1807); Brontë (1847); Golding (1954); Davis (2011); Munzer (2012). The FBI Database for tracking violent crimes against children is called, “Innocence Lost” (http://www.fbi.gov/about-us/investigate/vc_majorthefts/cac/innocencelost). The International Movie Database lists 467 films with the theme of innocence and innocence lost.

  2. To be clear, I do not mean to investigate particular innocence, or the status of not being morally responsible for a particular act. This kind of innocence applies to individuals qua moral agents who have an excuse or justification for what they have done and are not, as a consequence, blameworthy in a particular set of circumstances. My task is to examine moral innocence as the status one has prior to becoming a moral agent in the moral community. We might call this status global or general innocence in contrast to local or particular innocence.

  3. This is not to say that ignorance does not play any role in moral innocence. However, the morally innocent are not “simply ignorant”.

  4. A general ability to see that events have moral significance does not require that an individual moral agent always correctly or actively utilizes that ability. Analogously, I maintain the ability to run even if I am not running at this moment, run awkwardly, or run without proper form.

  5. For additional characterizations of the moral community as a conversation see, Gary Watson (1987) and Michael McKenna (2012).

  6. In a conversation there are a variety of appropriate responses in a given context. Once can declare, inquire, exclaim, and so on. For more on appropriate ways of using language given specific contexts, see Austin (1962).

  7. My focus in this essay is on the ability or inability, and not on the willingness or unwillingness.

  8. See also, R. Jay Wallace (1994).

  9. This example is borrowed from Fischer and Ravizza (1998, p. 208). The boy’s wrongdoing is admittedly quite mild. Nevertheless, the example helpfully draws our attention to a moral innocent who is capable of wronging another, and who maintains an illusory conception of the moral order.

  10. Although the two models cohere generally, Kohlberg disagrees with Piaget regarding how many stages of moral development a child goes through. Piaget’s model has two stages: roughly, before 10 to 12 years of age children see rules as fixed and tend to focus on consequences. Later on they see rules as permutable to allow for exceptions, and tend to focus on intention. Kohlberg’s findings lead him to posit six stages of moral development that start with rule-following and end with a recognition of individual rights and universal principles.

  11. For more on the psychology of moral development, see: Kohlberg (1981); Kohlberg et al. (1983); Gibbs et al. (1992); Langford (1995); Hoffman (2000); Gibbs (2003); Killen and Smetana (2006); Popper (2013).

  12. Slote (2013), pp. 66–71.

  13. For other philosophy texts that connect moral innocence with moral purity see: Murdoch (1976); Slote (1983); Wolgast (1993).

  14. See Hebrews 7:26; Proverbs 20:9; Psalms 26:6, 73:13; Exodus 23:7; Philippians 4:8; 2 Cor 11:2

  15. However, Hanson does not go so far as to claim that this interpretation is ex post facto. It is not a mental state applying a principle to an experience just had.

  16. One might worry that there is an epistemic level confusion here. There is an added third party objective standard about the truth of there being a nebula. However, this is precisely the reason to distinguish to seeing from seeing that. The child clearly sees a nebula despite lacking the ability to name it or correctly list its essential properties. This is why she does not see that it is a nebula. Her inability to name it properly is a direct result of her inability to see that it is a nebula. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for this point.

  17. Additionally, I might imagine how to go on to bring about wrongdoing or evil. I can imagine what the worst consequences for someone else would be, how a vicious person might act, or imagine a different way of life in order to act cruelly or disrespectfully. Thus, the moral imagination need not lead one to be morally good. It can easily lead to wickedness. It does, however, give one the ability to go beyond a simple knowledge of good and bad, and to question why knowledge of good and bad can be indeed ‘simple’.

  18. For more on this notion, see Kekes (2006).

  19. See Morris (1976) and French (1992) for more on the suggestion that the loss of moral innocence includes the recognition of one’s own ability to wrong others.

References

  • Austin, J. L. (1962). How to do things with words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blake, W. (1789). Songs of innocence and songs of experience. Champaign, Ill: Project Gutenberg. eBook Collection (EBSCOhost), EBSCOhost. Accessed September 30, 2014.

  • Brontë, C. (1847). Wuthering heights. Champaign, Ill: Project Gutenberg eBook Collection (EBSCOhost), EBSCOhost. Accessed September 30, 2014.

  • Davis, R. (2011). Brilliance of a fire: innocence, experience, and the theory of childhood. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 45(2), 379–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • French, P. (1975). ‘Seeing’ and ‘seeing that’, ‘observing’ and ‘observing that’. American Philosophical Quarterly Monograph Series: Studies in Epistemology no. 9, 89–97.

  • French, P. (1992). Responsibility matters. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, J. (2003). Moral development and reality: Beyond the theories of Kohlberg and Hoffman. Thousand Oaks: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, J., Basinger, K., & Fuller, D. (1992). Moral maturity: Measuring the development of sociomoral reflection. Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Golding, W. (1954). Lord of the flies. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, N. R. (1965). Patterns of discovery. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, M. (2000). Empathy and moral development. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, P. (1988). Politics, innocence and the limits of goodness. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kekes, J. (2006). The enlargement of life: Moral imagination at work. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Killen, M., & Smetana, J. (Eds.). (2006). Handbook of moral development. Mahwah: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg, L. (1981). The philosophy of moral development: Moral stages and the idea of justice. San Francisco: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg, L. (1984). Essays on moral development: Vol 2, the psychology of moral development. San Francisco: Harper & Row.

  • Kohlberg, L., Levine, C., & Hewer, A. (1983). Moral stages: A current formulation and a response to critics. New York: Karger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langford, P. (1995). Approaches to the development of moral reasoning. Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2008). The loss of innocence and the things that remain. APA Newsletter, 7(2), 5–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2012). Conversation and responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morris, H. (1976). On guilt and innocence: Essays in legal philosophy and moral psychology. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munzer, S. (2012). Innocence. Faith and Philosophy, 29(2), 125–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murdoch, I. (1976). The bell. St. Albans: Triad/Panther.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1932/1965). The moral judgment of the child. New York: Free Press.

  • Popper, S. (2013). Rethinking superhero and weapon play. New York: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M. (1983). Goods and virtues. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M. (2013). From enlightenment to receptivity: Rethinking our values. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. (1974). Freedom and resentment and other essays. London: Meuthen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urmson, J. O. (1958). Saints and heroes. In A. I. Melden (Ed.), Essays in moral philosophy. Seattle: University of Washington Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, R. J. (1994). Responsibility and the moral sentiments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, G. (1987). Responsibility and the limits of evil: Variations on a strawsonian theme. In F. Schoeman (Ed.), Responsibility, character, and the emotions: New essays in moral psychology (pp. 256–286). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigations, trans. G.E.M. Anscombe. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (1982). Moral saints. Journal of Philosophy, 79(8), 419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolgast, E. (1993). Innocence. Philosophy, 68(265), 297–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wordsworth, W. (1807). Ode: Intimations on immortality In Poems of William Wordsworth. Hoboken, N.J.: BiblioBytes. eBook Collection (EBSCOhost), EBSCOhost. Accessed September 30, 2014.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Zachary J. Goldberg.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Goldberg, Z.J. Moral Innocence as Illusion and Inability. Philosophia 43, 355–366 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-014-9580-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-014-9580-4

Keywords

Navigation