Skip to main content
Log in

“No Composition, No Problem: Ordinary Objects as Arrangements”

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

On the grounds that there are no mereological composites, mereological nihilists deny that ordinary objects (such as tables and chairs) exist. Even if nihilism is true, however, I argue that tables and chairs exist anyway: for I deny that ordinary objects are (identical to) the mereological sums the nihilist rejects. Instead, I argue, ordinary objects have a different nature; they are arrangements, not composites. My argument runs as follows. First, I defend realism about ordinary objects by showing that there is something that plays the role of ordinary objects in perception and discourse, and that ordinary objects are (identical to) whatever plays this role. Next, I argue that it is arrangements that play this role. It follows that ordinary objects exist- even if mereological nihilism is true.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For defenses of nihilism, see Rosen and Dorr (2002), Dorr (2005), and Cameron (2008, 2010).

  2. Many of these traditional views have modern variants. For a modern version of the bundle theory, see Paul (2006). For a modern take on Aristotelian hylemorphism, see Fine (2003, 2008) and Koslicki (2008). Others advocate newer conceptions. For objects as spacetime nodes, see Schaffer (2009). For discussion of objects as structural relations, see Chakravartty (2003). For objects as conventional constructions, see Sidelle (2010, inter alia). In brief, many candidates for the nature of objects exist, and each requires argument. That being said, I will neither defend nor criticize these particular theories (space forbids a thorough examination); rather, I mention them to establish precedent and a position in conceptual space.

  3. See Hirsch (2002) and McGrath (2008) for discussion of a distinct (but similar) linguistic (rather than metaphysical) principle of charity.

  4. Just as Quine (1948) slid between the name ‘Pegasus’ and the predicate ‘pegasizes’, the analogous move can be made here, mutatis mutandis.

  5. I assume—uncontroversially, I hope—that an instance of e.g., roundness is numerically distinct from the object which is round. Thus, more generally, an instance of a property being spatiotemporally located is distinct from the property-possessor being spatiotemporally located.

  6. Regarding the persistence conditions of arrangements in general, I do not here offer any general theory. For the most part, though, the sortal-governance of persistence conditions can be employed; the sorts of changes a tablewise arrangement can undergo are the very same changes a table might undergo, for example.

  7. Potential energy and gravitational force are perhaps more familiar examples of something’s causal powers depending on its (spatial) relations to other entities.

  8. Cf. Elder (2007), who runs a similar (though more complex) argument against nihilism based on the implausibility of referring to entities—atoms—too small to be perceived.

  9. Put another way: because mereology is supposed to be ontologically neutral—i.e., it is not supposed to matter whether something is composed out of e.g., properties or objects or abstracta—then whether we are talking of composite arrangements or more standard understood composites should not matter here.

  10. It should be noted that Merricks argues for the existence of people on the grounds that they are not causally redundant.

  11. This presentation largely follows Lewis (1993: 64).

  12. For Lewis (1993), supervaluationism is a way to recover in conversational contexts the (super) truth of ‘there is at most one cloud here’. Metaphysically, though, this is no solution, as it remains true (just not supertrue) that there are many clouds.

  13. For overviews and bibliographies, see Paul (2010) and Wasserman (2012).

  14. Paul considers this a kind of bundle theory, but with the familiar mereological notion of fusion replacing the more traditional (and perhaps more obscure) notions of compresence or bundling.

  15. Paul’s view need not be right to work here; instead, what is important is showing that the power of an extant view can be harnessed to do work for the objects-as-arrangements thesis.

References

  • Armstrong, D. (2004). Truth and truthmakers. Cambridge University Press.

  • Bennett, K. (2004). Spatiotemporal coincidence and the grounding problem. Philosophical Studies, 118(3), 339–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, K. (1981). The metaphysic of abstract particulars. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 6(1), 477–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, R. (2008). Truthmakers and ontological commitment: or how to deal with complex objects and mathematical ontology without getting into trouble. Philosophical Studies, 140(1), 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, R. (2010). How to have a radically minimal ontology. Philosophical Studies, 151, 249–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2003). The structuralist conception of objects. Philosophy of Science, 70, 867–878.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorr, C. (2005). What we disagree about when we disagree about ontology, In Kalderon, M. (ed.): Fictionalism in Metaphysics, Oxford Press: 234–286.

  • Elder, C. (2007). On the phenomenon of ‘dogwise arrangement’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74(1), 132–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2003). The non-identity of a material thing and its matter. Mind, 112, 195–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2008). Coincidence and form. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Xxxii, 101–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirsch, E. (2002). Quantifier variance and realism. Philosophical Issues, 12, 51–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1992). Multiple realization and the metaphysics of reduction. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1993). In Heil & Mele (Eds.), The non-reductivist’s troubles with mental causation. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki, K. (2008). The structure of objects. Oxford University Press.

  • Lewis, D. (1993). In Bacon (Ed.), Many, but almost one, in ontology, causality and mind: Essays in honour of D M Armstrong. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, M. (2008). Conciliatory metaontology and the vindication of common sense. Noûs, 42(3), 482–508.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (2001). Objects and persons. Oxford Press.

  • Paul, L. A. (2006). Coincidence as overlap. Noûs, 40(4), 623–659.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L. A. (2010). The puzzles of material constitution. Philosophy Compass, 5, 579–590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1948). On what there is. Review of Metaphysics, 2(5), 21–36. Reprinted in (1980): From A Logical Point of View, 1–19. Harvard University Press, 2nd edition.

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1951). Ontology and ideology. Philosophical Studies, 2, 11–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. and Dorr, C. (2002). Composition as a fiction. In Gale, R. (ed.): The Blackwell Guide to Metaphysics, Blackwell Press: 151–174.

  • Schaffer, J. (2009). Spacetime the one substance. Philosophical Studies, 145, 131–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sidelle, A. (2010). Modality and objects. Philosophical Quarterly, 60(238), 109–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. (1980). The problem of the many. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5, 411–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1990). Material beings. Cornell University Press.

  • Wasserman, R. (2012). Material constitution. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2012 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/entries/material-constitution/>.

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Cathy Sutton, Matt McGrath, Dan Korman, Tommy Kivatinos, Ben Abelson, and an audience at NYU’s Metaphysics Bootcamp for helpful discussion.

Ethical Statement

This manuscript complies with the ethical responsibilities outlined in the ‘Instructions for Authors’ portion of your website. In particular, this manuscript has not been submitted to more than one journal for simultaneous consideration, it has not been previously published in whole or in part, and it contains no plagiarism or unacknowledged sources. In addition, this work is free from any conflicts of interest (or appearances thereof).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jonah P. B. Goldwater.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Goldwater, J.P.B. “No Composition, No Problem: Ordinary Objects as Arrangements”. Philosophia 43, 367–379 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-015-9593-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-015-9593-7

Keywords

Navigation