Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Why expect causation at all? A pessimistic parallel with neuroscience

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In their target article, Lynch, Parke, and O’Malley argue against the quick application of causal, interventionist explanatory frameworks to microbiomes and their purported role in many disparate states, from obesity to anxiety. I think the authors have undersold the force of their argument. A careful consideration of the scope of their claims, made easier by a parallel drawn from the history of explanation in neuroscience, yields a productive pessimism: that causal explanations likely operate at the wrong level of analysis for dynamic, distributed, Quineian entities like the microbiome. That is, we shouldn’t expect causal explanations for microbiomes at all—and this includes the authors’ own “microbiome success story” of C. difficile. Neuroscience, with its own computationally challenging, dynamic entity—the brain—may provide lessons for how to approach something like predictive control over the microbiome.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Enterotypes might turn out to be a twenty-first century star-chart, with many internet services helping you “find your enterotype” and matching you to a probiotic blend that they conveniently stock.

  2. For instance, you could train a decoding model to predict, given a pattern of neural activation, which stimulus was most likely present. Likewise, you could train an encoding model to do the opposite. Applying statistical learning techniques, including Bayesian strategies, can further the predictive power of these models, as Schoenmakers et al. (2013) demonstrate.

References

  • Arumugam M, Raes J et al (2011) Enterotypes of the human gut microbiome. Nature 473:174–180

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bakken JS, Borody T et al (2011) Treating Clostridium difficile infection with fecal microbiota transplantation. Clin Gastroenterol Hepatol 9:1044–1049

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barlow HB (1953) Summation and inhibition in the frog’s retina. J Physiol 119:69–88

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barlow HB (1972) Single units and sensation: a neuron doctrine for perceptual psychology. Perception 1:371–394

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buffie CG, Bucci V et al (2015) Precision microbiome reconstitution restores bile acid mediated resistance to Clostridium difficile. Nature 512:205–208

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duncan J (2001) An adaptive coding model of neural function in prefrontal cortex. Nat Rev Neurosci 2:820–829

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fiorentini C, Fabbri A et al (1998) Clostridium difficile toxin B induces apoptosis in intestinal cultured cells. Infect Immun 66(6):2660–2665

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J (1983) The modularity of mind. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haynes J (2009) Decoding visual consciousness from human brain signals. Trends Cognit Sci 13(5):194–202

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haynes J (2015) A primer on pattern-based approaches to fMRI: principles, pitfalls, and perspectives. Neuron 87:257–270

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hubel DH, Wiesel TN (1962) Receptive fields, binocular interaction and functional architecture in the cat’s visual cortex. J Physiol 166:106–154

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein C (2014) The brain at rest: what is it doing and why it matters. Philos Sci 81:974–985

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearce JMS (2009) Marie–Jean–Peire Flourens (1794–1867) and cortical localization. Eur Neurol 61(5):311–314

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Postle BR (2015) Neural bases of the short-term retention of visual information. In: Jolicoeur P, Lefebvre C, Martinez-Trujillo J (eds) Mechanisms of sensory working memory: attention and performance XXV. Academic Press, London, pp 43–58

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rafter N (2008) Somatotyping, antimodernism, and the production of criminological knowledge. Criminology 45(4):805–833

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schoenmakers S, Barth M, Heskes T, Van Gerven M (2013) Linear reconstruction of perceived images from human brain activity. Neuroimage 83:951–961

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stein RR, Bucci V et al (2013) Ecological modeling from time-series inference: insight into dynamics and stability of intestinal microbiota. PLoS Comput Biol 9(12):1–11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Voth DE, Ballard JD (2005) Clostridium difficile toxins: mec of action and role in disease. Clin Microbiol Rev 18(2):247–263

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Javier Gomez-Lavin.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This comment refers to the article available at https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-019-9702-2.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gomez-Lavin, J. Why expect causation at all? A pessimistic parallel with neuroscience. Biol Philos 34, 61 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-019-9713-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-019-9713-z

Keywords

Navigation