Skip to main content
Log in

Linguistically invariant inductive logic

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Summary

Carnap's early system of inductive logic make degrees of confirmation depend on the languages in which they are expressed. They are sensitive to which predicates are, in the language, taken as primitive. Hence they fail to be ‘linguistically invariant’. His later systems, in which prior probabilities are assigned to elements of a model rather than sentences of a language, are sensitive to which properties in the model are called primitive. Critics have often protested against these features of his work. This paper shows how to make his systems independent of any choice of primitive predicates or primitive properties.

The solution is related to another criticism of inductive logic. It has been noticed that Carnap's systems are too all-embracing. Hisc(h, e) is defined for all sentencesh ande. Yet for manyh ande, the evidencee does not warrant any assessment of the probability ofh. We need an inductive logic in whichc(h, e) is defined only whene really does bear onh. This paper sketches the measure theory of such a logic, and, within this measure theory, provides ‘relativized’ versions of Carnap's systems which are linguistically invariant.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Bibliography

  1. Max Black, ‘Notes on the Paradoxes of Confirmation’, inAspects of Inductive Logic (ed. by Jaakko Hintikka and Patrick Suppes), Amsterdam 1966, pp. 175–197.

  2. Rudolf Carnap,The Continuum of Inductive Methods, Chicago 1952.

  3. Rudolf Carnap,The Logical Foundations of Probability, Chicago 1950.

  4. Rudolf Carnap, ‘Replies and Expositions’, V, inThe Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (ed. by P. Schilpp), La Salle, Illinois, 1963, pp. 966–998.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Nelson Goodman,Fact, Fiction, and Forecast, London 1954.

  6. Ian Hacking,The Leibniz-Carnap Programme, forthcoming.

  7. David Hume,A Treatise on Human Nature (ed. by L. A. Selby-Bigge), Oxford, 1888.

  8. Harold Jeffreys,Theory of Probability, 3rd ed., Oxford 1961.

  9. C. R. Karp,Languages with Expressions of Infinite Length, Amsterdam 1964.

  10. J. M. Keynes,A Treatise on Probability, London 1921.

  11. Johannes von Kries,Die Principien der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechung, Freiburg 1886.

  12. P. S. de Laplace, ‘Mémoires sur la probabilité des causes par les événements’,Mémoires de l'Academie Royale des Sciences, vol.VI, 1774, pp. 621–656. In theOeuvres, vol.VIII, p. 30 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ernest Nagel, ‘Carnap's Theory of Induction’ inThe Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (ed. by P. Schilpp), La Salle, Illinois, 1963, pp. 785–825.

    Google Scholar 

  14. W. V. Quine,Methods of Logic, Cambridge, Mass., 1950.

  15. A. Renyi, ‘On a New Axiomatic Theory of Probability’,Acta Mathematica 6, 285–332.

  16. W. C. Salmon, ‘Carnap's Inductive Logic’,The Journal of Philosophy 21 (1967) 725–740.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Dana Scott and Peter Krauss, ‘Assigning Probabilities to Logical Formulas’ inAspects of Inductive Logic (ed. by Jaakko Hintikka and Patrick Suppes), Amsterdam 1966, pp. 219–264.

  18. W. Stegmüller, ‘Anhang B’ inInduktive Logik und Wahrscheinlichkeit (ed. by Rudolf Carnap and W. Stegmüller), Vienna 1958, pp. 242–252.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Hacking, I. Linguistically invariant inductive logic. Synthese 20, 25–47 (1969). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00567234

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00567234

Keywords

Navigation