Skip to main content
Log in

A normative framework for argument quality: argumentation schemes with a Bayesian foundation

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, it is argued that the most fruitful approach to developing normative models of argument quality is one that combines the argumentation scheme approach with Bayesian argumentation. Three sample argumentation schemes from the literature are discussed: the argument from sign, the argument from expert opinion, and the appeal to popular opinion. Limitations of the scheme-based treatment of these argument forms are identified and it is shown how a Bayesian perspective may help to overcome these. At the same time, the contributions of the standard scheme-based approach are highlighted, and it is argued that only a combination of the insights of different traditions will yield a complete normative theory of argument quality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In first instance, probabilities—as degrees of belief—are subjective, and the probability calculus is about coherence, in the same way that classical logic is about the relationships between statements, not their truth or falsity per se. However, it is typically assumed that a rational agent should adopt as her subjective degree of belief objective probabilities (limit frequencies) where these are defined, see e.g., Lewis (1980).

  2. Posterior odds convert into posterior degrees of belief via the simple relationship \(P(A) = Odds(A)/(1+Odds(A))\).

  3. This is not to say, however, that alternative frameworks have not been put forward, see e.g., Schum (1994).

  4. For continuous variables correlation is defined as \({\textit{rAB}}=\frac{E(A,B)-E(A)E(B)}{\sqrt{E(A^{2})-(E(A)})^{2}\sqrt{E(B^{2})-(E(B))^{2}}}\) where E(A) is the expected value of A, Specifically, independence implies zero correlation, but the converse is not necessarily true. Variables can be systematically related, and hence non-independent, in ways not captured by (linear) correlation (e.g., x and y in \({y=sin(x)}\)). This also suggests that independence, as the more general notion, is preferable to correlation as the basis for the argument from sign.

  5. \(P(A{\vert }B)=P(A,B)/P(B)\)

  6. To put this more formally, one might think of a generalization such as “If A, then generally B” as saying that \({P(B{\vert }A)}\) is high. On observing A, the probability we should now assign to B will be \({P(B{\vert }A)}\), exactly as (defeasible) modus ponens suggests. However, whether A provides a reason for believing B, depends on whether \({P(B{\vert }A)}\) is greater than P(B) in the first place, and that depends on the likelihood ratio being greater than 1, i.e., that \({P(B{\vert }A) > P(B{\vert } \lnot A)}\). On modus ponens and other conditional inferences from a probabilistic perspective see e.g., Oaksford and Chater (1994), Evans and Over (2004) and, specifically in an argumentation context Hahn and Oaksford (2012).

  7. Bayesian Belief Networks simplify multi-variable computations by taking into account dependence and independence relations within a graphical representation (for an introduction see e.g., Pearl 1988 or Korb and Nicholson 2003). The nodes in a network such as that in Fig. 2 represent random variables. The directed arrows (links) between them signify (assumed) direct causal influences and the strengths of these influences are quantified by conditional probabilities. Each variable is assigned a link matrix that represents estimates of the conditional probabilities of the events associated with that variable given any value combination of the parent variables’ states. These matrices together provide a joint distribution function: a complete and consistent global model, on the basis of which all probabilistic queries can be answered.

  8. Within the scheme-based tradition Hastings (1962, p. 143) also considers both schemes to be related to “causal relations which are used as generalizations to justify the conclusion on the basis of the premises”.

  9. Further examples of the dissociation between logical validity and inductive strength to those given thus far are the so-called paradoxes of material implication, see Oaksford and Hahn (2007).

  10. These seem largely based on consideration of characteristics of probability in the context of logical inference, rather than, as advocated here, Bayesian conditionalization. For example, Pollock’s arguments about how multiple, independent, premises lead rapidly to improbable conclusions assume that the relationship between premises and conclusions is conceived of as a logical inference from a conjunction, not as a conditional probability. In general, believing more things does not inherently imply greater risk of error, see e.g., Bovens and Olsson (2002).

  11. Hahn and Oaksford (2007b) argue, among other things, that the notion of burden of proof is inherently tied to action, stemming in law from the need to make a decision. Where a decision is required, the utilities associated with various courses of action provide ‘burdens of proof’. Where a decision is not immediately required, the notion is forced, and there are no normatively compelling reasons for determining either levels of proof required, or who should carry them.

  12. Carneades can handle such accrual of evidence for cumulative arguments if an argument for every member of the powerset of the pieces of evidence is included in the argument graph, see also Gordon and Walton (2009).

  13. By contrast, Walton and Gordon (2014) explicitly highlight ‘relevance’ as a key issue that still needs to be formally modelled within Carneades.

  14. This is not to deny that there may be contexts, such as the law, in which distinguishing between being ‘in a position to know’ and ‘being expert’ might be meaningful (see e.g., Godden and Walton 2006). However, in order to justify different argument schemes there must minimally be some consequential difference to either the basic inference or the critical questions.

References

  • Alexy, R. (1989). A theory of legal argumentation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson, D., & Peijnenburg, J. (2010). Justification by infinite loops. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 51, 407–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F., Prakken, H., Reed, C., & Walton, D. (2003). Towards a formal account of reasoning about evidence: Argumentation schemes and generalisations. Artificial Intelligence and Law, 11, 125–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, C. M. (2006). Pattern recognition and machine learning. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolstad, W. M. (2004). Introduction to Bayesian statistics. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bovens, L., & Hartmann, S. (2003). Bayesian epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bovens, L., & Olsson, E. J. (2002). Believing more, risking less: On coherence, truth and non-trivial extensions. Erkenntnis, 57, 137–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chater, N., Tenenbaum, J. B., & Yuille, A. (2006). Probabilistic models of cognition: Conceptual foundations. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10, 287–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christmann, U., Mischo, C., & Flender, J. (2000a). Argumentational integrity: A training program for dealing with unfair argumentational contributions. Argumentation, 14, 339–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christmann, U., Mischo, C., & Groeben, N. (2000b). Components of the evaluation of integrity violations in argumentative discussions: Relevant factors and their relationships. Journal of Language and Social Psychology, 19, 315–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clemen, R. T. (1989). Combining forecasts: A review and annotated bibliography. International Journal of Forecasting, 5, 559–583.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corner, A., & Hahn, U. (2009). Evaluating science arguments: Evidence, uncertainty, uncertainty, and argument strength. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied, 15, 199–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corner, A., & Hahn, U. (2013). Normative theories of argumentation: Are some norms better than others? Synthese, 190, 3579–3610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corner, A., Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2011). The psychological mechanism of the slippery slope argument. Journal of Memory and Language, 64, 153–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Condorcet, N. C. (1785). Essai sur l’Application de l’Analyse à la Probabilité des Décisions Rendues à la Pluralité des Voix. Paris: Imprimerie Royale.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1984). Cognitive wheels: The frame problem of AI. In C. Hookaway (Ed.), Minds, machines and evolution (pp. 129–151). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eagly, A. H., & Chaiken, S. (1993). The psychology of attitudes. Belmont, CA: Thompson/ Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. (1992). Bayes or bust?. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehninger, D. (1974). Influence, belief, and argument: an introduction to responsible persuasion. Glenview, IL: Scott Foresman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehningner, D., & Brockriede, W. (1963). Decision by debate. New York: Dodd, Mead.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J. St B T., & Over, D. E. (2004). If. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, R., & Well, A. D. (1997). Many faces of the correlation coefficient. Journal of Statistics Education, 5(3), 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitelson, B. (1996). Wayne, Horwich and evidential diversity. Philosophy of Science, 63, 652–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forsythe, R., Nelson, F., Neumann, G. R., & Wright, J. (1992). Anatomy of an experimental political stock market. The American Economic Review, 82, 1142–1161.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, J., & Das, S. (2000). Safe and sound. Menlo Park: AAAI Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, J. B. (1995). The appeal to popularity and presumption by common knowledge. In H. V. Hansen & R. C. Pinto (Eds.), Fallacies: Classical and contemporary readings (pp. 263–273). University Park: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galton, F. (1907). Vox populi. Nature, 75, 450–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garssen, B. J. (1997). Argumentatieschema’s in pragma-dialectisch perspectief: Een theoretisch en empirisch onderzoek. Amsterdam: IFOTT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigone, D., & Hastie, R. (1997). Proper analysis of the accuracy of group judgments. Psychological Bulletin, 121, 149–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godden, D. M., & Walton, D. N. (2006). Argument from expert opinion as legal evidence: Critical questions and admissibility criteria of expert testimony in the American legal system. Ratio Juris, 19, 261–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, K. (1924). Group judgments in the field of lifted weights. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 7, 398–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, T. F., & Walton, D. (2009). Proof burdens and standards. In I. Rahwan & G. Simari (Eds.), Argumentation in artificial intelligence (pp. 239–260). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, T., Prakken, H., & Walton, D. (2007). The Carneades model of argument and burden of proof. Artificial Intelligence, 171, 875–896.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, D. M., & Swets, J. A. (1966). Signal detection theory and psycho-physics. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grofman, B., Owen, G., & Feld, S. L. (1983). Thirteen theorems in search of the truth. Theory and Decision, 15, 261–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U. (2011). The problem of circularity in evidence, argument and explanation. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 6, 172–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U. (2014). The Bayesian boom: Good thing or bad? Frontiers in Cognitive Science, 5, Article 765.

  • Hahn, U., Harris, A. J. L., & Corner, A. J. (2009). Argument content and argument source: An exploration. Informal Logic, 29, 337–367.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2006a). A Bayesian approach to informal argument fallacies. Synthese, 152, 207–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2006b). Why a normative theory of argument strength and why might one want it to be Bayesian? Informal Logic, 26, 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2007a). The rationality of informal argumentation: A Bayesian approach to reasoning fallacies. Psychological Review, 114, 704–732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2007b). The burden of proof and its role in argumentation. Argumentation, 21, 39–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2012). Rational argument. In Holyoak & Morrison (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of thinking and reasoning. Oxford: Oxford university Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., Oaksford, M. & Bayindir, H. (2005). How convinced should we be by negative evidence? In Proceedings of the 27th annual meeting of the cognitive science society.

  • Hahn, U., Oaksford, M., & Harris, A. J. (2013). Testimony and argument: A Bayesian perspective. In F. Zenker (Ed.), Bayesian argumentation (pp. 15–28). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Hajek, A. (2008). Dutch book arguments. In P. Anand, P. Pattanaik, & C. Puppe (Eds.), The handbook of rational and social choice (pp. 173–196). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, C. L. (1970). Fallacies. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardman, D. (2009). Judgment and decision making: Psychological perspectives. Chichester: BPS Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, A. J. L., Corner, A., & Hahn, U. (2013). James is polite and punctual (and useless): A Bayesian formalisation of faint praise. Thinking & Reasoning, 19, 414–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, A. J. L., Hahn, U., Hsu, A. S., & Madsen, J. K. (2015). The appeal to expert opinion: Quantitative support for a Bayesian network approach. Cognitive Science.

  • Harris, A. J. L., Hsu, A. S., & Madsen, J. K. (2012). Because Hitler did it! Quantitative tests of Bayesian argumentation using ad hominem. Thinking and Reasoning, 18, 311–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hastings, A. C. (1962). A reformulation of the modes of reasoning in argumentation. Unpublished dissertation, Northwestern University, Evanston, IL.

  • Hoeken, H., Sorm, E., & Schellens, P. J. (2014). Arguing about the likelihood of consequences: Laypeople’s criteria to distinguish strong arguments from weak ones. Thinking and Reasoning, 20, 77–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoeken, H., Timmers, R., & Schellens, P. J. (2012). Arguing about desirable consequences: What constitutes a convincing argument? Thinking and Reasoning, 18, 394–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hogarth, R. (1978). A note on aggregating opinions. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance, 21, 40–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hornikx, J., & Hoeken, H. (2007). Cultural differences in the persuasiveness of evidence types and evidence quality. Communication Monographs, 74, 443–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C., & Urbach, P. (1993). Scientific reasoning: The Bayesian approach. La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inch, E. S., & Warnick, B. H. (2009). Critical thinking and communication: The use of reason in argument (6th ed.). Boston: Pearson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joensson, M., Hahn, U. & Olsson, E. (2015). The kind of group you want to belong to: Effects of group structure on group accuracy. Cognition. Online first.

  • Kadane, J. B., & Schum, D. A. (1996). A probabilistic analysis of the Sacco and Vanzetti evidence. Chichester: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katzav, J., & Reed, C. A. (2004). On argumentation schemes and the natural classification of arguments. Argumentation, 18, 239–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kienpointner, M. (1992). Alltagslogik: Struktur und Funktion von Argumentationsmustern. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Friedrich Frommann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knill, D. C., & Richards, W. (Eds.). (1996). Perception as Bayesian inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korb, K. (2004). Bayesian informal logic and fallacy. Informal Logic, 23, 41–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korb, K. B., & Nicholson, A. E. (2003). Bayesian artificial intelligence. Boca Raton: CRC Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korb, K. B., McConachy, R. & Zukerman, I. (1997). A cognitive model of argumentation. In: Proceedings of the 19th annual conference of the cognitive science society (pp. 400–405).

  • Ladha, K. K. (1992). The Condorcet jury theorem, free speech, and correlated votes. American Journal of Political Science, 36, 617–634.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laplace, P. S. (1951). A philosophical essay on probabilities (F. W. Truscott & F. L. Emory, Trans.). New York: Dover Publications. (Original work published 1814).

  • Leitgeb, H., & Pettigrew, R. (2010). An objective justification of Bayesianism II: The consequences of minimizing inaccuracy. Philosophy of Science, 77, 236–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1980). A subjectivist’s guide to objective chance. In Richard C. Jeffrey (Ed.), Studies in inductive logic and probability (Vol. II, pp. 263–293). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorge, I., Fox, D., Davitz, J., & Brenner, M. (1958). A survey of studies contrasting the quality of group performance and individual performance, 1920–1957. Psychological Bulletin, 55, 337–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McConachy, R., & Zukerman, I. (1999). Towards a dialogue capability in a Bayesian argumentation system. ETAI 3—Electronic Transactions of Artificial Intelligence (Section D), 3, 89–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • McConachy, R., Korb, K. B., & Zukerman, I. (1998). Deciding what not to say: An attentional-probabilistic approach to argument presentation. In Proceedings of the 20th annual conference of the cognitive science society (pp. 669–674), Madison, Wisconsin.

  • Mercier, H., & Sperber, D. (2011). Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34, 57–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myrvold, W. C. (1996). Bayesianism and diverse evidence: A reply to Andrew Wayne. Philosophy of Science, 63, 661–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, E. M. (2011). Argumentation, dialogue theory, and probability modeling: Alternative frameworks for argumentation research in education. Educational Psychologist, 46, 84–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, E. M., & Edwards, O. V. (2011). Critical questions and argument stratagems: A framework for enhancing and analyzing students’ reasoning practices. Journal of Learning Sciences, 20, 443–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Keefe, D. J. (2002). Persuasion: Theory and research (2nd ed.). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oaksford, M., & Chater, N. (1994). A rational analysis of the selection task as optimal data selection. Psychological Review, 101, 608–631.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oaksford, M., & Hahn, U. (2004). A Bayesian approach to the argument from ignorance. Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology, 58, 75–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oaksford, M., & Hahn, U. (2007). Induction, deduction and argument strength in human reasoning and argumentation. In A. Feeney, & E. Heit (Eds.), Inductive reasoning (pp. 269–301). Cambridge University Press.

  • Olsson, E. J. (2002). What is the problem of coherence and truth? Journal of Philosophy, 94, 246–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, E. J., & Schubert, S. (2007). Reliability conducive measures of coherence. Synthese, 157, 297–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, E. J. (2005). Against coherence: Truth, probability, and justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Page, S. E. (2005). The difference: How the power of diversity creates better groups, firms, schools, and societies. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (1988). Probabilistic reasoning in intelligent systems. San Mateo, CA: Morgan Kaufman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, C., & Olbrechts-Tyteca, L. (1969). The new rhetoric: A treatise on argumentation. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petty, R. E., & Cacioppo, J. T. (1986). Communication and persuasion: Central and peripheral routes to attitude change. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. L. (1995). Cognitive carpentry: A blueprint for how to build a person. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H. (2005). AI & law, logic and argument schemes. Argumentation, 19, 303–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H., & Vreeswijk, G. A. W. (2002). Logics for defeasible argumentation. In D. M. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic (2nd ed., Vol. 4, pp. 219–318). Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rahwan, I., & Simari, G. R. (Eds.). (2009). Argumentation in artificial intelligence. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reed, C., & Rowe, G. (2004). Araucaria: Software for argument analysis, diagramming and representation. International Journal of Artificial Intelligence Tools, 13, 961–980.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reinard, J. C. (1991). Foundations of argument: Effective communication for critical thinking. Dubuque, IA: William C. Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1976). Plausible reasoning. Assen: Van Gorcum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieke, R. D., & Sillars, M. O. (1984). Argumentation and the decision making process. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenkrantz, R. D. (1992). The justification of induction. Philosophy of Science, 59, 527–539.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellens, P. J. (1985). Redelijke argumenten: Een onderzoek naar normen voor kritische lezers. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schum, D. A. (1994). The evidential foundations of probabilistic reasoning. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snoeck Henkemans, A. F. (2000). State-of-the-art: The structure of argumentation. Argumentation, 14, 447–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stroop, J. R. (1932). Is the judgment of the group better than that of the average member of the group? Journal of Experimental Psychology, 15, 550–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Surowiecki, J. (2004). The wisdom of crowds. New York, NY: W.W. Norton & Company Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Treynor, J. L. (1987). Market efficiency and the bean jar experiment. Financial Analysts Journal, 43, 50–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2004). A systematic theory of argumentation. The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. (2003a). Dialectical argumentation with argumentation schemes: Towards a methodology for the investigation of argumentation schemes. In F. H. van Eemeren, A. Blair, C. Willard, & F. Snoeck Henkemans (Eds.), Proceedings of the 5th conference of the international society for the study of argumentation (pp. 1033–1037). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. (2003b). Deflog: On the logical interpretation of prima facie justified assumptions. Journal of Logic and Computation, 13, 319–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verheij, B. (2004). Dialectical argumentation with argumentation schemes: An approach to legal logic. Artificial intelligence and Law, 11, 167–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1989). Informal logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1996). Argumentation schemes for presumptive reasoning. Mahwah, N.J.: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1997). Appeal to expert opinion: Arguments from authority. University Park, PA: Penn State Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1998). The new dialectic: Conversational contexts of argument. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

  • Walton, D. N. (1999). Appeal to popular opinion. University Park, PA: Penn State Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. M. (2001). Abductive, presumptive, and plausible arguments. Informal Logic, 21, 141–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (2004). Relevance in argumentation. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (2006). Fundamentals of critical argumentation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (2008). Witness testimony evidence: Argumentation, artificial intelligence, and law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D., & Gordon, T. F. (2005). Critical questions in computational models of legal argument. In P. E. Dunne, & T. Bench-Capon (Ed.), International workshop on argumentation in artificial intelligence and law (pp. 103–111). Nijmegen: Wolf Legal Publishers.

  • Walton, D., & Gordon, T. F. (2014). How to formalize informal logic. In Mohammed, D., & Lewiński, M. (Eds.), Virtues of argumentation. In: Proceedings of the 10th international conference of the Ontario society for the study of argumentation (OSSA), 22–26 May 2013(pp. 1–13). Windsor, ON: OSSA.

  • Walton, D., & Reed, C. (2002). Argumentation schemes and defeasible inferences. In Workshop on computational models of natural argument, 15th European conference on artificial intelligence (pp. 11–20).

  • Walton, D. N., Reed, C., & Macagno, F. (2008). Argumentation schemes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wayne, A. (1995). Bayesianism and diverse evidence. Philosophy of Science, 62, 111–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whately, R. (1846). Elements of rhetoric: Comprising an analysis of the laws of moral evidence and of persuasion, with rules for argumentative composition and elocution/c by Richard Whately. B. Fellowes.

  • Woods, J., Irvine, A., & Walton, D. N. (2004). Argument: Critical thinking, logic and the fallacies, Revised Edition. Toronto: Prentice Hall.

  • Zukerman, I. (2009). Towards probabilistic argumentation. In I. Rahwan & G. R. Simari (Eds.), Argumentation in artificial intelligence (pp. 443–462). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Frank Zenker for helpful comments on a draft of this manuscript, and Tom Gordon for helpful discussion.The first author was partially supported by the Swedish Research Council’s Hesselgren professorship, and the second author was partially supported by the Centre for Language Studies (Nijmegen).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ulrike Hahn.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

There are no potential conflicts of interest associated with this research.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hahn, U., Hornikx, J. A normative framework for argument quality: argumentation schemes with a Bayesian foundation. Synthese 193, 1833–1873 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0815-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0815-0

Keywords

Navigation