Skip to main content
Log in

The strategic gene

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Gene-selectionists define fundamental terms in non-standard ways. Genes are determinants of difference. Phenotypes are defined as a gene’s effects relative to some alternative whereas the environment is defined as all parts of the world that are shared by the alternatives being compared. Environments choose among phenotypes and thereby choose among genes. By this process, successful gene sequences become stores of information about what works in the environment. The strategic gene is defined as a set of gene tokens that combines ‘actor’ tokens responsible for an effect with ‘recipient’ tokens whose replication is thereby enhanced. This set of tokens can extend across the boundaries of individual organisms, or other levels of selection, as these are traditionally defined.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A gene’s effects are often measured relative to the average for all alternatives (alleles) in the population. Fisher (1941) defined the average effect as the partial regression of the phenotypic measure on the presence or absence of the gene.

  2. A function is synonymous with a selectional property of a gene (Shea 2007, p. 320) or the property for which there is selection (Sober 1984, pp. 99–100). In Sober’s example of small green balls passing through a sieve, there was selection for the property of smallness and selection of objects that were small and green. He did not state whether there was selection of the property of greenness. I consider there to be selection for and of functions of a favored gene but simply selection of side-effects.

  3. Many significant things do not have precise boundaries. No line on the ground demarcates where the Rocky Mountains begin (nor is there any way to count the number of peaks in Colorado without making pragmatic, somewhat arbitrary, choices about what counts as a peak). One could, if one chose, think of North America as comprised of smaller and larger chunks of landscape material without naming any topographical features with fuzzy boundaries. Locations and areas could be identified by latitude and longitude, but this would be cumbersome. Natural selection is pragmatic rather than principled (whatever ‘works’ works) and my own approach to evolutionary theory is similarly pragmatic.

  4. Dichotomous branching is a property of the semi-conservative replication of DNA but is not a necessary feature of the genealogies of genes. Rabies virus has a single-stranded RNA genome. This strand is transcribed to produce the complementary single-stranded antigenome that serves as a template to transcribe multiple copies of the parent genome (Wunner 2007).

  5. A strategic gene could also consist of tokens (actors) that reduced the replication of tokens of the same type (recipients), but in this case the strategy is inept and the gene would be eliminated by natural selection.

  6. Isadore Nabi (pers. comm.) offers the rejoinder “If we could explain how each organism has evolved its particular form, by the selection of differences, then we would have explained, per stirpes, why it has its particular state. But the reverse is not true. A sufficient explanation of how an organism develops may tell us nothing about why it has its particular form.”

  7. Fisher (1958, p. 39), a statistician par excellence, compared his fundamental theorem of natural selection to the second law of thermodynamics. Dynamics exhibits ‘time-reversal invariance’ whereas thermodynamics is not time-reversible. Processes of mutation, drift and recombination are time-reversible at the micro-level of the individual gene token but increase entropy at the population level. Fisher believed that natural selection was associated with a unidirectional arrow of time that tended to increase order. Okasha (2008, p. 346) rejects the existence of such an arrow because increase in ‘adaptation’ is countered by deterioration in the environment.

  8. Here I employ a loose definition of replication and heritability as recurrence of form, including the ‘simple replicators’, ‘limited hereditary replicators’, and ‘unlimited hereditary replicators’ of Maynard Smith and Szathmáry (1995, pp. 41–42).

References

  • Bacolla A, Ulrich MJ, Larson JE, Ley TJ, Wells RD (1995) An intramolecular triplex in the human γ-globin 5′-flanking region is altered by point mutations associated with hereditary persistence of fetal hemoglobin. J Biol Chem 270:24556–24563

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergstrom CT, Rosvall M (2011) The transmission sense of information. Biol Philos 26:159–176

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouchard F, Rosenberg A (2004) Fitness, probability and the principles of natural selection. Br J Philos Sci 55:693–712

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R, Richerson PJ, Henrich J (2011) The cultural niche: why social learning is essential for human adaptation. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 108:10918–10925

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1982) The extended phenotype. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (2011) Homunculi rule: reflections on Darwinian populations and natural selection by Peter Godfrey-Smith. Biol Philos 26:475–488

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ewens WJ (2011) What is the gene trying to do? Br J Philos Sci 62:155–176

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA (1941) Average excess and average effect of a gene substitution. Ann Eugen 11:53–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA (1958) The genetical theory of natural selection, 2nd edn. Dover, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank SA (2009) Natural selection maximizes fisher information. J Evol Biol 22:231–244

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner A, Welch JJ (2011) A formal theory of the selfish gene. J Evol Biol 24:1801–1813

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray R (1992) Death of the gene: developmental systems strike back. In: Griffiths P (ed) Trees of life: essays in philosophy of biology. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 165–209

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (1998) What is the developmentalist challenge? Philos Sci 65:253–258

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haig D (1997) The social gene. In: Krebs JR, Davies NB (eds) Behavioural ecology, 4th edn. Blackwell Scientific, Oxford, pp 284–304

    Google Scholar 

  • Haig D (2003) Meditations on birthweight: Is it better to reduce the variance or increase the mean? Epidemiology 14:490–492 (erratum Epidemiology 14:632)

    Google Scholar 

  • Haig D (2006) The gene meme. In: Grafen A, Ridley M (eds) Richard dawkins. How a scientist changed the way we think. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 50–65

    Google Scholar 

  • Haig D (2007) Weismann rules! OK? Epigenetics and the Lamarckian temptation. Biol Philos 22:415–428

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haig D (2008) Huddling: brown fat, genomic imprinting, and the warm inner glow. Curr Biol 18:R172–R174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haig D (2010) The huddler’s dilemma: a cold shoulder or a warm inner glow. In: Székely T, Moore AJ, Komdeur J (eds) Social behaviour: genes, ecology and evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 107–109

    Google Scholar 

  • Haig D, Trivers R (1995) The evolution of parental imprinting: a review of hypotheses. In: Ohlsson R, Hall K, Ritzen M (eds) Genomic imprinting: causes and consequences. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 17–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (1974) The analysis of variance and the analysis of causes. Am J Hum Genet 26:400–411

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin RC (2000) Foreword. In: Oyama S (ed) The ontogeny of information, 2nd edn. Duke University Press, Durham, pp vii–xv

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J, Szathmáry E (1995) The major transitions in evolution. W. H. Freeman, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Muller HJ (1934) Variation due to change in the individual gene. Am Nat 56:32–50

    Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S (2008) Fisher’s fundamental theorem of natural selection—a philosophical analysis. Br J Philos Sci 59:319–351

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson M (1961) The logic of collective action. Public goods and the theory of groups. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama S (2000) The ontogeny of information. Developmental systems and evolution, 2nd edn. Duke University Press, Durham

    Google Scholar 

  • Queller DC (2011) A gene’s eye view of Darwinian populations. Biol Philos 26:905–913

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandhu KS, Shi C, Sjölinder M, Zhao Z, Göndör A, Liu L et al (2009) Nonallelic transvection of multiple imprinted loci is organized by the H19 imprinting control region during germline development. Genes Dev 23:2598–2603

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea N (2007) Representation in the genome and in other inheritance systems. Biol Philos 22:313–331

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1984) The nature of selection. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E, Wilson DS (1994) A critical review of philosophical work on the units of selection problem. Philos Sci 61:534–555

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K, Griffiths PE (1999) Sex and death. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K, Kitcher P (1988) The return of the gene. J Philos 85:339–361

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K, Smith KC, Dickison M (1996) The extended replicator. Biol Philos 11:377–403

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sturtevant AH (1915) The behavior of the chromosomes as studied through linkage. Z indukt Abstam Vererbungs 13:234–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams GC (1966) Adaptation and natural selection. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams GC (1986) Comments on Sober’s The nature of selection. Biol Philos 1:114–122

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson DS, Sober E (1994) Reintroducing group selection to the human behavioral sciences. Behav Brain Sci 17:585–654

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wunner WH (2007) Rabies virus. In: Jackson AC, Wunner WH (eds) Rabies, 2nd edn. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 23–68

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Daniel Dennett, Steve Frank, Andy Gardner, Peter Godfrey-Smith, Kim Sterelny and the Fundamental Interconnectedness of All Things discussion group made helpful comments on the manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Haig.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Haig, D. The strategic gene. Biol Philos 27, 461–479 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-012-9315-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-012-9315-5

Keywords

Navigation