Skip to main content
Log in

A Conundrum Concerning Creation

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I expose a conundrum regarding divine creation as Leibniz conceives of such creation. What energizes the conundrum is that the concept of omnibenevolence—“consequential omnibenevolence”—that the Leibnizian argument for the view that the actual world is the best of all possible worlds presupposes, appears to sanction the conclusion that God has no practical reasons to create the actual world.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for e.g., (Leibniz 1975).

  2. I (like many others) take the Leibnizian argument seriously. To analyze it, one need not, for instance, work with something like a “maximally complete concepts” analysis of possible worlds that a Leibnizian may favor. My approach, then, is not strictly historical. I might depart, at various junctures, from what we find in the Leibnizian texts about the Creation Argument. Still, a theorist who thinks this intriguing argument has merit may want to know how strong the argument is independently of what Leibniz had to say about it.

  3. See, for e.g., Hoffman and Rosenkrantz (2002).

  4. For further restrictions on what an omnipotent being can do, see Rosenkrantz and Hoffman (1980).

  5. See Feldman (1986). Suppose that for every world accessible to A at t, there is a better one then accessible to A as well. To handle this possibility, Feldman advances the following as the official version of world utilitarianism: as of t, A ought to see to the occurrence of p if and only if p occurs in some world accessible to A at t, and it is not the case that not-p occurs in any accessible world as good as or better than that one (1986, p. 38.)

  6. In a different (forthcoming) work, I argue that an omniscient being cannot have knowledge of propositions that predict the occurrence of undetermined future contingent events. If this is so, I argue, further, that God cannot know the value of certain “free worlds,” worlds that contain some such undetermined events. This spells trouble for the creation argument assuming that there are “free worlds.”

  7. Not everyone accepts the view that God is essentially omnibenevolent. See, for example, Pike (1969). Not everyone accepts the view that ‘omnibenevolence’ can be defined. For instance, consult Wierenga (1989).

  8. See, for example, Wierenga’s discussion in The Nature of God: An Inquiry into Divine Attributes, p. 203.

  9. Leibniz seems to have believed that the criterion of goodness for possible worlds validates the ontological claim that there is a best. The best possible world, Leibniz says, is one that exhibits the greatest variety of phenomena compatible with the greatest simplicity of its laws. See Theodicy, sec. 208; and (Leibniz 1902).

  10. For a recent defense of the “ought” implies “can” principle, see, for e.g., Zimmerman (1996), Chap. 3, sec. 3.1; and Haji 2002.

  11. On Frankfurt-type examples, see Frankfurt (1969).

  12. Further defense of the view that there is a requirement of alternative possibilities for the truth of judgments of moral obligation can be found in Haji 2002.

  13. A number of theorists accept the moral “ought” implies “can” principle; other theorists reject it. As I have argued, this principle, in conjunction with certain others, entails that “ought” implies “can refrain” as well. Conceding that some do not accept these principles but acknowledging that others do, it would still be useful to inquire about, for instance, whether we can have moral obligations in a world in which, perhaps because deterministic, we cannot do otherwise. Both parties would learn something from this exercise.

  14. In section 5 below, I argue that scenarios in which God selects among optimals is not cost-free.

  15. See, for e.g., Zimmerman’s The Concept of Moral Obligation, Chap. 2.

  16. For further discussion on the point that there is no world in which an essentially C-omnibenevolent being brings about anything that is wrong, see Hoffman (1979); and Morriston (1985).

  17. See, for e.g., Plantinga (1974); and Adams (1972).

  18. See, for instance, Hoffman and Rozenkrantz, The Divine Attributes, pp. 147–152; and Haji 1994.

  19. Theodicy, Part 1, sec. 8.

  20. In “Must God Create The Best?,” Adams argues that assuming some non-consequentialist principle of morality is true, God could create a non-best without wronging any of His creatures or failing in kindness to any of them.

References

  • Adams, R. M. (1972). Must God create the best. Philosophical Review, 81, 317–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, F. (1986). Doing the best we can: An essay in informal deontic logic (p. 37). Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. G. (1969). Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility. Journal of Philosophy, 66, 829–839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haji, I. (1994). Consequential Ominbenevolence. Grazer Philosophisce Studien, 24, 207–222.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haji, I. (2002). Deontic Morality and Control. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, J. (1979). Can God do evil. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 17, 213–220, p. 216, paper.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, J., & Rosenkrantz, G. S. (2002). The Divine attributes (pp. 112–113). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz (1902). Discourse on Metaphysics, Correspondence with Arnauld, Monadology, translated by George Montgomery. La Salle, Ill.: Open Court Publishing Company, secs. 5 and 6.

  • Leibniz, G. W. (1951). Theodicy, edited and with an introduction by Austin Farrer, translated by E.M. Huggard (pp. 267–268). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

  • Leibniz (1975). In G. H. R. Parkinson (Ed.), Philosophical Writings, translated by Mary Morris and G. R. Parkinson (pp. 112, 211). Totowa, N.J.: Rowman & Littlefield.

  • Morriston, W. (1985). Is God significantly free. Faith and Philosophy, 2, 257–264, p. 258, piece.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pike, N. (1969). Omnipotence and God’s ability to sin. American Philosophical Quarterly, 6, 208–216, pp. 208–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1974). The nature of necessity (pp. 169–190). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenkrantz, G. S., & Hoffman, J. (1980). What an omnipotent agent can do. International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, 11, 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wierenga, E. R. (1989). The nature of God: An inquiry into Divine attributes (pp. 202–203). Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, M. J. (1996). The concept of moral obligation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ishtiyaque Haji.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Haji, I. A Conundrum Concerning Creation. SOPHIA 48, 1–14 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-008-0062-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-008-0062-7

Keywords

Navigation