Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-tj2md Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T03:37:19.768Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Motivations for Relativism as a Solution to Disagreements

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 July 2013

Abstract

There are five basic ways to resolve disagreements: keep arguing until capitulation, compromise, locate an ambiguity or contextual factors, accept Pyrrhonian skepticism, and adopt relativism. Relativism is perhaps the most radical and least popular solution to a disagreement, and its defenders generally think the best motivator for relativism is to be found in disputes over predicates of personal taste. I argue that taste predicates do not adequately motivate relativism over the other possible solutions, and argue that relativism looks like the most promising approach when disputants cannot even agree on the meta-evidence for a contested proposition.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 2013 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 James, William, Pragmatism, a New Name For Some Old Ways of Thinking (New York: Longman, Green, and Co. 1907) 4345CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Kölbel, Max, ‘“True” as Ambiguous’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77:2. (2008), 359384CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 Sosa, Ernest, A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Sosa, Ernest, Reflective Knowledge: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 John MacFarlane, ‘Varieties of Disagreement’, forthcoming, draft, 2009.

5 Mates, Benson, The Skeptic Way, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), 89Google Scholar.

6 Ibid., 5.

7 A somewhat similar approach is dialethic logic. Unlike relativism, which regulates contradictions by allowing p and not-p to both be true so long as they are in different perspectives, dialethism forgoes perspectives and embraces true contradictions straight up. Relativism is compatible with classical logic (I argue in Relativism and the Foundations of Philosophy (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2006)Google Scholar that a suitable relativist logic is a monotonic extension of ordinary modal logic), but dialethism explicitly is not. It is also debatable whether dialethism allows disagreement. For some discussion of this latter point, see Priest, Graham, In Contradiction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2nd ed. 2006.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, §20.4. I think it is clear that dialethism is more controversial than relativism and that whatever else might said for it, irreconcilable differences alone will not motivate it over relativism.

8 Lewis, David, On the Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986), 212213Google Scholar.

9 Rovane, Carol, ‘Relativism Requires Alternatives, Not Disagreement or Relative Truth’ in Hales, Steven D. (ed.), A Companion to Relativism (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2011)Google Scholar; Boghossian, Paul, ‘Three Kinds of Relativism’ in Hales, Steven D. (ed.), A Companion to Relativism (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2011)Google Scholar.

10 MacFarlane, John, ‘Relativism and Disagreement’, Philosophical Studies 132 (2007), 29CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11 McGinn, Colin, The Problem of Consciousness (Blackwell, Oxford, 1991)Google Scholar.

12 Wright, Crispin, ‘Intuitionism, Realism, Relativism, and Rhubarb’ in Greenough, Patrick, & Lynch, Michael P (eds), Truth and Realism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), 41Google Scholar.

13 Kölbel, Max, ‘Faultless Disagreement’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 104:1 (2004), 53Google Scholar.

14 Op. cit. note 10, 39.

15 Op. cit. note 11, 58–9, cf. Euthyphro 7b–c.

16 Op. cit. note 8, 17.

17 For a recent critical study and meta-analysis, see Rhodes, Gillian, ‘The Evolutionary Psychology of Facial Beauty’, Annual Review of Psychology 57:1 (2006), 199226CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

18 Although there is also evidence that characteristic preferences are evolutionary spandrels related to information processing. See Ibid., 7.18–7.19.

19 Kim, Jaegwon, Philosophy of Mind (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1996.), 4Google Scholar.

20 Ancestors of this paper were presented at the Institute of Philosophy in the School of Advanced Studies at the University of London, the 6th Conference of the Spanish Society for Analytic Philosophy, and the University of Western Michigan. Many thanks for the constructive comments at those venues. Completion of this work has been granted by Spanish Government (Ministerio de Economía y Competividad), Research Projects FFI2008-01205. Puntos de Vista. Una Investigación Filosófica and FFI2011-24549. Puntos de vista y estructuras temporales.