1 Introduction

Contemporary social ontologists typically reject the notion that social groups (such as book clubs, street bands and faculty committees) can be reductively identified with pluralities, sets or fusions of individuals. Instead, they hold that social groups are sui generis entities constituted or composed by, or grounded in, collections of individuals, and that these constitution/composition/grounding relations are asymmetric dependence relations distinct from n-adic identity relations. Surprisingly absent from these discussions is an alternative position which involves neither reductive identification nor the postulation of ontic sui generis entities. The alternative I have in mind is to theorise social groups—or rather, truths about them—in terms of deflationary truthmakers. In this paper I provide a sketch of this approach. Potentially, the approach allows us to say, with traditional ontological individualists, that there are only pluralities of individuals out there, ontologically speaking, but that there are nevertheless colloquial and social-scientific truths about social groups. Thus, if it is tenable, this kind of theory has the virtue of being both ontologically parsimonious and compatible with ordinary and social-scientific discourse.

The structure of the paper is as follows. In Sect. 2, I set out the standard objections to the (now unpopular) stock reductive identifications. In Sect. 3, I summarise difficulties for the ontological dependence accounts of social groups. Both of these sections are very concise. In Sect. 4, I outline my own deflationary truthmakers account of social groups and show how it avoids the difficulties canvassed in the two preceding sections. In Sect. 5, I address potential objections to the approach. I end with some concluding remarks in Sect. 6.

2 Difficulties with the Stock Reductive Identifications

It is generally agreed among social ontologists that what we, as social ontologists, are after is a metaphysical account of social groups which allows us to maintain, in line with colloquial and social-scientific discourse, the following (theses (1–5) below might even be regarded by some as expressing non-negotiable Moorean truthsFootnote 1):

Social groups

  1. (1)

    are single things or units;

  2. (2)

    are located in space and time;

  3. (3)

    begin to exist when the members are suitably interrelated, or engage in certain activities, or are related to an appropriate external phenomenon;

  4. (4)

    can change members over time; and

  5. (5)

    can coincide membership-wise with distinct social groups.

However, if social groups are reductively identified with pluralities/sets/fusions of individuals, it becomes hard to maintain all of (1–5).Footnote 2 The difficulties here have been discussed thoroughly in the literature.Footnote 3 I will sum them up, relegating more detailed comments to the footnotes. My aim is not to prove that all of the stock identifications fail. I wish merely to give a sense of what the main problems are in order to motivate interest in alternatives to reductive identifications.

First, if we identify social groups with pluralities of individuals, we face difficulties with (1), (3), (4), and (5). Picking up these difficulties in turn, we can observe that: pluralities are precisely not single things, but several things (viz., two or more); ‘a plurality’ of individuals, a, b, c, will typically predate the formation of the relevant group (i.e., the relevant individuals typically all exist before they engage in the relevant activity or become suitably related); if individual a is, but individual d is not, one of a, b, c, then arguably a cannot cease to be, and d cannot become, one of a, b, c (i.e., arguably, pluralities cannot change members over time); and distinct pluralities cannot consist of the same members (mutual inclusion) on pain of becoming identical (e.g. Oliver & Smiley, 2016: p. 109).Footnote 4

If we identify social groups with sets of individuals, difficulties arise with (2), (3), (4), and (5). Again, taking the issues in turn, we can point out that: sets are traditionally conceived of as abstract; a set of individuals {a, b, c} exists irrespective of how the elements a, b, c are related; sets are not changeable entities; and distinct sets cannot have the same elements.Footnote 5

Finally, if we identify social groups with fusions (mereological sums) of individuals, (3), (4), and (5) are problematic: a fusion of individuals typically exists before the relevant individuals are suitably related; a fusion of individuals, as standardly conceived, cannot change summands over time; and distinct fusions of individuals cannot consist of the same parts.Footnote 6

3 Difficulties for Ontological Dependence Theories

The problems outlined above have led many social ontologists to suggest that social groups should be characterised as entities composed of, or grounded in, or constituted by pluralities/sets/fusions of (interrelated) individuals (typically, by distinct pluralities/sets/fusions at distinct times), and that the various ontological dependence relations should be treated as distinct from n-adic identity relations (e.g. Uzquiano, 2004; Sawyer, 2005; Baker, 2007, 2019; List & Pettit, 2011; Hindriks, 2013; Lawson, 2013; Elder-Vass, 2014; Ritchie, 2013, 2020; Epstein, 2015, 2019; Fine, 2020; Passinsky, 2021).Footnote 7

However, ontological dependence theories of social groups have their own difficulties. Again, the literature contains extensive discussion of these, and the aim of my summary is only to give a sense of the issues, in order to motivate search for alternatives.Footnote 8 As before, more detailed comments are relegated to footnotes.

  1. (a)

    Ontological dependence theories are not ontologically parsimonious. Apart from individuals who may engage in certain activities and stand in certain relations (and perhaps sets or fusions of such individuals), such theories postulate entities (social groups) which are numerically distinct from, and hence additional to, the suitably interrelated individuals (or sets/fusions thereof). Ceteris paribus, we should prefer ontologically simple theories.Footnote 9

  2. (b)

    In effect, such theories postulate a level of being over and above the individualistic level. On this view, there is one level consisting of (suitably related) individuals; ‘on top’ of that level there is another consisting of social groups numerically distinct from the individuals on the first level. If social groups in their turn are said to compose/constitute/ground higher level social groups or social entities, even higher levels are postulated.Footnote 10 (And if fusions are postulated, there will be a level in between the individualistic level and the social-group level.) Among other things, this levelled ontology creates a causal exclusion problem in the social realm, analogous to the much-discussed causal exclusion problem in the philosophy of mind (cf. Kim, 2005).Footnote 11

  3. (c)

    Such theories entail that new ontic entitiesFootnote 12 (social groups) begin to exist in the world—at a level ‘higher up’ than the level of pre-existing individuals—when the individuals in question engage in certain activities, or become suitably interrelated or related to an appropriate external phenomenon. For example, a street band comes into existence as a new higher-level ontic entity when several individuals start playing instruments in a coordinated way on a street. A book club comes into existence as a new higher-level ontic entity when several individuals start thinking of each other as belonging to a common book club. And a faculty committee comes into existence as new higher-level ontic entity when the appropriate process of appointing has taken place at the relevant university. But it is just incredible that new higher-level things (social groups) can ‘pop’ into existence in the external world simply because individuals begin to play instruments, think of each other in a certain way, or perform certain declarative speech acts. Worse, such creations may even involve backwards causation or generation, at least in the case of appointments, if the relevant speech acts or act are performed with a retroactive force: for example, if it is declared, at some time t1, that individuals a, b, c, …., are to be members of a specific group (a faculty committee, say) from time t0 (where t0 is before t1).Footnote 13

  4. (d)

    The persistence of social groups seems often to be partly a matter of convention or decision. The faculty committee is a striking example: whether such a committee, created in the past, still exists after, say, a membership change, may depend on what is stated in the relevant regulation (and this may differ between different faculties/universities, and even across time within one faculty/university) or on what further speech acts are performed by some relevant authorised person/s at the university in question.Footnote 14But the notion that the persistence of an ontic entity can be a matter of convention is highly dubious.Footnote 15 This is so whether ontic objects persist by enduring, exduring or perduring. If ontic objects persist by enduring (by being wholly present at distinct times as numerically the same entity) their persistence can hardly be a matter of convention as the identity relation is arguably an internal relation that holds of necessity (if it holds). Likewise, if they persist by exduring (by having distinct temporal counterparts at distinct times) their persistence can hardly be a matter convention as the temporal counterpart relation, an external relation, cannot plausibly be stipulated into existence—irrespective of whether it is a non-supervenient relation à la Hawley (2001) or a relation that supervenes on spatiotemporal, causal and similarity relations à la Sider (2001). Finally, if ontic objects persist by perduring (by having distinct temporal parts at distinct times) their persistence can hardly be a matter of convention: four-dimensional aggregates of temporal parts simply have the spatiotemporal extensions that they have—these cannot be legislated at will.Footnote 16

4 An Unexplored Alternative: The Deflationary Truthmakers Approach

It would be valuable, then, to develop an alternative account of social groups – one that does not involve reductive identification and avoids the problems besetting ontological dependence theories. I will now argue that a deflationary truthmakers account can fill this role.

The starting point of the deflationary approach is the general idea, often endorsed by truthmaker theorists (e.g. Armstrong, 2004: pp. 32–34), that many of the statements or propositions that we take to be true are made true by entities or facts quite different from those we expect (when, at least, we take the statements at face value). The statements or propositions have deflationary truthmakers – i.e., truthmakers that do not, at first sight, look fully ‘dressed up’ for the occasion, but which nevertheless suffice to make the relevant statement true (ibid.: p. 33). A few examples will illustrate the general idea.

Truthmaker B-theorists (e.g. Mellor, 1998) maintain that although tensed statements like ‘Ann ran yesterday’ appear to be made true by A-facts involving temporal A-properties (such as being one day past), they are in fact made true by B-facts involving temporal B-relations (relations such as being before/after/simultaneous with) and no A-properties. Similarly, truthmaker categoricalists (e.g. Armstrong, 2004) assert that while dispositional statements like ‘this material is corrosive’ seem to be made true by the subject’s possession of a dispositional property or power, they are actually made true by the subject’s instantiation of an intrinsically inert categorical property governed by contingent laws of nature. Deflationists about rainbows (as we may call them) hold that statements like ‘there is a rainbow east of us’ are made true, not by rainbows, but by sunlight-reflecting raindrops (e.g. Mellor, 2009/2012, who strictly speaking claims that rainbow statements are made true ‘indirectly’ by sunlight-reflecting raindrops, ibid.: p. 104). And truthmaker deflationists about macroscopic objects and properties in general, maintain that the statements that look as if they are made true by such entities, such as ‘this brick is rectangular’, are in fact made true by fundamental particles arranged in certain ways (e.g. Cameron, 2008, 2010).Footnote 17 If these philosophers are right, the relevant truths do not entail that there are, in an ontological or ontic sense, any A-properties, powers, rainbows, or even any macroscopic objects and properties. Thus, truthmakers need not exactly ‘mirror’ the content of the truths in question (cf. Heil, 2003: p. 189). An alternative way of expressing this point is to maintain that truthmaker theories are not committed to ‘truth as correspondence’ – not even in relation to positive, contingent truths (see Mellor, 2009/2012 and David, 2022 for further discussion).Footnote 18

In what follows, I shall assume for the sake of convenience that there really are macroscopic objects and individuals, instantiating properties and relations ‘out there’ in an ontic sense (what this amounts to will be discussed below—for a brief, initial explanation, see note 12 above). These entities will be among the suggested truthmakers for truths about social groups. However, in principle I am open (see my 2014b) to the idea that, in the end, we should only refer to fundamental particles or fields as truthmakers—although this is certainly not practically possible at the moment (at least, not for me, given my very limited knowledge of the relevant physics and the workings of our brains, or of the entities ‘arranged brainwise’).

In very rough outline, then, what I propose is this. I begin with thesis (3), the idea (or Moorean truth) that social groups begin to exist when individuals engage in certain activities, or are suitably interrelated or related to an appropriate external phenomenon. Using the examples of social groups I gave earlier, I suggest the following. When several individuals start playing music in a coordinated way on a street, or start thinking of each other as members of a book club, or are elected and appointed in accordance with the relevant rules and regulations at a faculty/university, it becomes true to say, respectively: ‘A street band has been formed [or created]’, ‘A book club has been formed [or created]’ and ‘A faculty committee has been formed [or created]’. The truthmakers for such statements, however, are not new ontic objects that have, as it were, popped into existence in the external world—a street band, a book club, a faculty committee—over and above the relevant related individuals. The deflationary truthmakers are simply these individuals, as they perform certain actions (playing their instruments on a street) or enter into certain states of mind (think of each other as members of a book club). Where statements about the creation of formal groups such as faculty committees are concerned, the relevant truthmakers also include, I suggest, formal regulations and the relevant speech acts (e.g. acts of voting and appointing). In these latter cases, the time of the relevant ‘creation’ and the times of the relevant speech acts may be separated by (quite considerable) time intervals. Further, the time of the ‘creation’ may even predate the times of the relevant speech acts, making it true to speak of ‘retroactive creation’. But since no ontic object is retroactively brought into being in such cases, no backwards causation is involved.Footnote 19

Plausibly the proposed deflationary truthmakers would need to be supplemented with further material to be collectively sufficient for truth, but whatever has to be added here (internal and external norms might be candidates, cf. Thomasson, 2019), the central idea is that irreducible ontic social groups do not have to be the truthmakers.Footnote 20

Turning to some clarifying, basic formalism, I would defend the following. Suppose we paraphrase a true ordinary language statement such as ‘A book club has now been formed’, made at time t1, along the lines of ‘(∃x) (FxLxt1 ∧ ¬Lxt0)’ (where F = _is a book club with such and such features, and L = _is located at time_, and t0 is an arbitrary time before t1).Footnote 21 On my view, the formalised version is false, given the objectual or referential interpretation of the existential quantifier (e.g. Quine, 1948/1980), simply because there are no F-objects to quantify over, at any time, in the objectual/referential (or, as I would put it, ontic) sense. Alternatively put: no F-entity can be reckoned as value of the variable ‘x’.Footnote 22 However, if a substitutional interpretation of the quantifier is adopted (e.g. Marcus, 1972/1993; Kripke, 1976; in which case the symbol ‘Σ’ is often used), the formalised version does express a truth, given that there is a true substitution instance of the form ‘FaLat1 & ¬Lat0’, as the existential quantifier, on this reading, says that there is (the formal language in question is assumed to have a suitable stock of names). The truthmakers for such a substitution instance are, I suggest, of the kind described above – they are individuals thinking of each other as members of a book club. Thus, on the view defended here, the term ‘a’, in such a substitution instance, does not refer to an ontic referent, a; nevertheless, the substitution instance is true, given that it has deflationary truthmakers of the kind described.Footnote 23

Thus, when, in ordinary language or social-scientific discourse, we say that a social group was created at a certain time, the claim should, if we want to formalise it, be paraphrased and interpreted along the latter, substitutional lines. Of course, often actual substitution instances are lackingFootnote 24 because no one has produced them (i.e., uttered or written them down—the putative group may even lack a name). But this is compatible with what I am suggesting. The commitment of an ordinary-language or social-scientific claim to the effect that a certain social group has been created should not be taken to be to actual ordinary/scientific-language names and substitution instances. We should merely be taken to be committed to the notion that we could have introduced a name, ‘G’ say, for ‘the created group’ in question (even if we did not actually do so) which would have allowed us to say—truly (given the deflationary truthmakers)G is a book club which…’. Further, the idea is that if we were to formalise this original claim and the appropriate substitution instances, a formal language explicitly containing substitutional first-order quantifiers and a suitable stock of names and predicates should be used (or developed).Footnote 25

I should perhaps highlight that my invocation of substitutional quantification sets me apart from standard truthmaker theorists. The typical truthmaker theorists does not make use of the distinction between objectual and substitutional quantifiers. I think, however, that this distinction helps to clarify how there can be existential truths about entities that do not ‘really’ exist (as, e.g., Cameron, 2008: 6 and Mellor, 2009/2012: 99 put it). Entities that do not ‘really’ exist are not ontic entities—they cannot be quantified over using objectual/referential existential quantifiers (∃). But, there may nevertheless be existential truths (such as ‘There are book clubs’) ‘about’ non-ontic entities – these truths, however, should be formalised in terms of substitutional existential quantifiers (Σ), and are made true by deflationary truthmakers.Footnote 26

Next, thesis (2), the idea (or Moorean truth) that social groups are spatiotemporally located. I have already indicated what makes it true to say, in ordinary English, that a social group has been created (and thus can be said to be located) in time: the deflationary truthmakers are, at least partly, suitably related individuals that exist in time. The relevant, related individuals are also, I suggest, deflationary truthmakers for statements about the relevant group’s spatial location(s). For example, what makes it true to say ‘The book club is currently gathered at Elm Street’ is that a sufficient number of members of the club have congregated at Elm Street; and what makes it true to say ‘The book club is currently dispersed all over the city’ is that enough members of the club are currently in locations all over the city; and so on.Footnote 27

On to thesis (4), the view (or Moorean truth) that social groups can change members over time. What are the truthmakers for particular statements about group-persistence through member-change? Since social groups are not genuine ontic entities on a deflationary truthmakers view, it is up to us to legislate ‘their’ persistence conditions. Such declarations (in their various forms, see below) are key truthmakers, I suggest, for statements about a particular social group’s persistence, including statements about its persistence through member change. The kind of persistence-statements I have in mind are simply common or garden statements such as ‘the group still exists’ and ‘the group has lasted a long time’. They are ordinary language statements which do not commit the speaker to a specific metaphysical view of persistence such as endurantism, exdurantism or perdurantism.

Consider the faculty committees, for example. These are formal groups whose persistence conditions—as noted above, and as pointed out by Epstein (2019)—often are governed by formal regulations at the relevant faculty or university (unless they are simply stipulated, on a case-by-case basis, by singular acts of declaration by some authorised person: for example, by way of a signature on a certain document expressing that a specific group is still active, although original members have been replaced). Epstein appears to think of the relevant regulation as an ‘anchor’ (his term) which determines the worldly persistence (including persistence through member change) of faculty committees, where those committees are understood as genuine, constituted, ontic entities. By contrast, on the view I am advancing here, the regulation is simply a truthmaker—along with the relevant worldly states of affairs ensuring that the persistence conditions stated in the regulation are fulfilled – of true statements about the relevant faculty committee’s persistence.Footnote 28

Of course, book clubs do not generally operate under regulations. Their persistence conditions are in effect decided upon informally, and somewhat circularly, by the members of the putative group itself (cf. Forsyth, 2019: p. 14). I suggest, then, that, what makes it true to say that a certain book club still exists following, say, a minor membership change is, at least in unexceptional cases, that a sufficient number of those who founded it, or some of the more influential individuals within the group, think of, or represent, certain contemporary individuals as members of the original book club, and thus think of the club as still existing despite the membership change – i.e. they accept that ‘it’ now consists of these individuals.

Spontaneously formed street bands are a little different.Footnote 29 Their persistence conditions are arguably established neither by formal regulation nor by their own members’ attitudes. The musicians here may simply be cheerful individuals who spontaneously start jamming at a city festival without knowing each other. The persistence conditions of such street bands appear to be specified—to the extent that they are—by how we in general tend to think and speak of such spontaneously formed social groups. I suspect our fairly unreflective practices here leave the persistence conditions of spontaneously formed street bands quite indeterminate. (Similar vagueness may characterise faculty committees and book clubs if the relevant regulation or the member-attitudes leave the persistence conditions indeterminate.) Thus, if a number of individuals in a spontaneously formed street band are replaced, or if the musicians have begun to walk in opposite directions, there may simply be no fact of the matter whether the original band still exists: that is, it may be indeterminate whether a statement to this effect is true. Suppose, however, that a statement with this content is definitely true on a specific occasion because the vague persistence conditions are clearly met. Then I suggest that the deflationary truthmakers will include—apart from the relevant background linguistic behaviour itself—the individuals and events that meet the conditions set up by the linguistic behaviour: for example, music-playing individuals at an appropriate spatial distance from each other, most of whom participated in the original ‘formation’ of the band. We do not need to postulate an irreducible ontic street band that has succeeded in enduring/exduring/perduring over the time interval in question as a truthmaker.

What about the claim of thesis (or Moorean truth) (1) that social groups are single things or units? When we conceptualise social groups as entities with persistence conditions that differ from those of pluralities—e.g., conditions allowing them to change members—we automatically construe them as single entities or units. Thus, I propose that among the deflationary truthmakers for a particular statement of the form ‘social group G is a single thing’ we find—apart from the several members of the group and their relations—the factors that are deflationary truthmakers for statements about G’s persistence conditions. As we have seen, where the faculty committee, book club and street band are concerned these factors include relevant regulations, speech acts, background linguistic behaviour and member-attitudes.

Finally, thesis (5), the idea (or Moorean truth) that distinct social groups can have the same members at the same time, even permanently. Here we can be very brief, I think. It will be true to say that the relevant co-membered groups are distinct if it is true to say either that they were ‘formed’ at distinct times (and here an account of the type outlined above, regarding thesis (3), can be applied) or that they are governed by distinct rules or norms (where the truthmakers may be distinct codes, statutes, by-laws, attitudes, mental representations, linguistic behaviours, etc., as the case might be).

My contention is, then, that the deflationary truthmakers approach to social groups is compatible with all of theses (or Moorean truths) (1–5), as well as being free of the difficulties afflicting ontological dependence theories.

5 Objections

At this point, someone who endorses the Eleatic Principle that (roughly speaking) to be is to make a causal difference (see Plato’s Sophist, 247e) may object as follows. Social groups are characterised as causal both in colloquial speech and in the social sciences. But to be causal social groups need to be real in the ontic sense, since it is the ontic sense of being with which the Eleatic Principle is concerned – at least, that is how modern metaphysicians and social ontologists typically understand the principle (see e.g. Armstrong, 2004: pp. 37–38—although he makes little explicit use of ‘∃’).

My response: not so quick! Elsewhere I have argued at length that we should distinguish between what I call ‘sparse causation’ and ‘mere abundant causation’ (Hansson Wahlberg 2022). Sparse causation is realised in the form of worldly processes that connect cause and effect, understood as ontic entities. Possible examples of it include physical interactions and the propagation of physical quantities (e.g. Salmon, 1984 and Dowe, 2000). Mere abundant causation obtains if a causal statement is true but the (putative) causal relata spoken of are not connected by some appropriate physical process (at least, not at the level in question). Examples of mere abundant causation include cases of negative causation. In these cases the ‘absence’ of something is often truly said to be a cause, as is the case in ‘the gardener’s failure to water the flowers caused the flowers to wither’ (see e.g. Schaffer, 2004).

The Eleatic Principle, if accepted, should be confined to sparse causation. Otherwise, given that there are causal truths involving absences, it will entail that absences are ontic entities (which is clearly problematic: see Mumford & Anjum, 2011 and my 2022 for discussion). And the account of social groups I have sketched is fully compatible with the idea that, although the members of social groups may participate in causal relationships of sparse kinds, social groups as such only participate in causal relationships of mere abundant kinds. To resist the Eleatic argument, therefore, we can accept that there may be causal truths about social groups, but point out that these truths do not have to correspond to any causal relationships of a sparse kind at some putative level of ontic social groups.Footnote 30

A second objection to the deflationary truthmakers account of social groups refers to rational group judgments (including group decisions) that may differ from what the majority of the relevant individuals would individually judge on the issue.Footnote 31 Suppose three individuals agree, or are obliged, to adopt a premise-based procedure when forming a collective judgment on a proposition (in effect, a conclusion) of the form ‘p and q’. Assume further that the premises simply are ‘p’ and ‘q’, and that individual 1 judges that ‘p’ is true and that ‘q’ is true, individual 2 judges that ‘p’ is true and that ‘q’ is false, and individual 3 judges that ‘p’ is false and that ‘q’ is true. A majority of the individuals (i.e., individuals 2 and 3, assuming that they are rational) will judge, individually, that the conclusion, ‘p and q’, is false. However, given that they have agreed to follow a premise-based procedure where the collective judgment on the conclusion is determined by how a majority of the individuals judge each of the premises, the collective judgment will be that the conclusion is true (since a majority think ‘p’ is true and a majority think ‘q’ is true). Thus, the collective judgement, on the premise-based procedure, will be that the conclusion is true even though a majority of the individuals think it is false. But – and this is the advantage of the procedure – with the premise-based procedure, the collective judgements on the premises and the conclusion will be internally consistent. The collective judgements could of course have been formed proposition-wise: collective judgements on the premises could have been made first, based on the individual judgements of the premises, and then a separate and additional judgement on the conclusion could have been made, based on the individual judgements of the conclusion. But then the collective judgements would have been inconsistent: the premises would have been judged true, but the conclusion false, despite the conclusion’s following from the premises. By adopting a premise-based procedure, the three individuals will judge and behave, collectively, as a rational, unified, autonomous agent (List & Pettit, 2011: pp. 69–70, pp. 76–78).

How does this bear on the topic of this paper? Some may think that in cases like this, we are forced to postulate social groups (even ‘groups with minds of their own’, ibid.: pp. 77–78) as truthmakers for statements such as ‘the group judged that the conclusion is true’. They may claim that we should therefore be ontic realists about groups (cf. ibid.: pp. 5–6). However, as far as I can see, the cases simply do not require us to postulate ontic social groups. To return to the example above, the truthmakers for the proposition ‘the group judged that the conclusion “p and q” is true’ are simply the individuals’ judgements on the premises (‘p’ and ‘q’) together with their acceptance – or the externally decreed ruling – of the premise-based procedure.Footnote 32

Finally, let me mention recently published criticism of the kind of view defended in this paper. In response to my truthmaker account of the creation and existence of corporations (see Hansson Wahlberg 2021), Asya Passinsky (2021) says that she largely agrees with the main points but that.

[the truthmaker view] should provide an account of what concrete social objects are, which elucidates why these things can be brought into existence by agreement and the like. The truthmaker view does not provide such an account, as its focus is on ordinary statements about social objects rather than the objects themselves. (Passinsky, 2021: p. 8)

I think this complaint misses the mark, since on the deflationary truthmakers approach to social objects, such as corporations and social groups, there are no social objects in an ontological sense. In other words, there can be no positive account of what they ‘are’ in a heavyweight sense. And it is precisely because they do not exist in an ontic sense that we should focus on ordinary statements about them, not ‘the objects themselves’. If we can provide a full and convincing account of what makes such statements true (including statements about how social objects are ‘brought into existence’) without having to postulate social objects as ontic entities, we will have done all that is required. In this paper on social groups, and in my earlier examination of corporations, my aim has been to explain, in a preliminary way, how deflationary truthmakers accounts of these two phenomena might be developed.

6 Conclusion

On the deflationary truthmakers approach to social groups there are no social groups in an ontic sense. There are nonetheless various truths about social groups. The deflationary truthmakers are essentially individuals doing various things and standing in various relations (sometimes to appropriate external phenomena). The approach is fully compatible with theses (or Moorean truths) (1)-(5). It also avoids various issues that weaken ontological dependence accounts. For these reasons, I believe the deflationary truthmakers approach to social groups deserves to be further investigated by social ontologists.