Skip to main content
Log in

The Relevance of Hannah Arendt’s Reflections on Evil: Globalization and Rightlessness

  • Published:
Human Rights Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The centenary of Hannah Arendt’s birth in 2006 has provided the catalyst for a body of literature grappling with the legacy of her thought, especially the question of its enduring political relevance. Yet this literature largely excludes from consideration a significant aspect of Arendt’s legacy, namely, her account of evil and its devastating political reality. This article contends that the neglect of Arendt’s understanding of the dynamic reality of evil unnecessarily delimits the opportunities her legacy affords to diagnose forms of evil today. In particular, I propose that Arendt’s notion of evil and her unique insight into its dynamic reality remain very much pertinent in light of a globalizing world where the conditions of extreme deprivation and exclusion have become thoroughly bound up with the structurally unequal conditions of the global political economy. The persistent global poverty knowingly reproduced in and through policies and practices of economic globalization effectively renders vast numbers of people superfluous and “rightless,” resulting in a distinctive form of political evil. I conclude that more attention should be paid to the deeper pertinence of Arendt’s concepts of evil, human superfluousness, and rightlessness for contemporary political life.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for example, the writings collected in Adorno (2003). For an insightful comparison of Arendt and Adorno on the Holocaust see Villa (2008, ch. 7).

  2. See also Arendt (1970, 56): “Marx’s great trust in the dialectical “power of negation”... rests on a much older philosophical prejudice: that evil is no more than a privative modus of the good, that good can come out of evil; that, in short, evil is but a temporary manifestation of a still-hidden good.”

  3. See Arendt’s discussion of Hermann Broch and the break between the pre- and post-totalitarian generations in Men in Dark Times (1968b, 125–27).

  4. While Arendt employed the term “radical” (or “absolute”) evil in The Origins of Totalitarianism, she later came to the conclusion that to speak of evil as “radical” is misleading since it implies some unfathomable metaphysical depth or “roots” beneath evil as it appears in human action (see 1978b, 251). Yet the “banality” of evil is not merely a substitute for “radical” evil. This is because Arendt continues to refer to “extreme” evil as well as the banality of evil. For Arendt, extreme evil refers to the actual dehumanization of people that makes them superfluous, while the banality of evil refers to the condition of “thoughtlessness” that enables “ordinary” persons to participate in policies and practices that result in extreme evil. For more on thoughtlessness as a lack of critical judgment and “enlarged thought,” see Arendt (1992).

  5. For an excellent discussion of postmetaphysical conceptions of evil see Lara (2007).

  6. The distinction between direct and indirect or structural violence, with the latter defined as avoidable or preventable oppression and death attributable to institutions and systems of power legitimized by prevailing norms, was first made by Johan Galtung; see Galtung (1969).

  7. This is a theme taken up recently by McCarthy (2009) in his analysis of neoracism and neoimperialism.

  8. Lines points out that standards of living around the world were broadly similar until the imperial era, and that existing severe global disparities have been deliberately produced and extended only throughout the past two hundred years. Also see Arendt’s extensive analysis of imperialism and its legacy within the modern international system, notable for its melding of power politics with the interests of capital and its expansionistic logic “based on maldistribution,” in the second volume of The Origins of Totalitarianism (2004, 168–209).

  9. For a trenchant critique of the way in which poverty is naturalized by the “market epistemology” of the global political economy, see Da Costa and McMichael (2007).

  10. A notable exception is Larry May (1996).

References

  • Adorno, Theodor W. 2003. Can One Live after Auschwitz? A Philosophical Reader, ed. Rolf Tiedemann, trans. Rodney Livingstone. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1958. The Human Condition, 2nd edn. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1963. On Revolution. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1965. Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil, rev. edn. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1968a. Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1968b. Men in Dark Times. San Diego, New York, and London: Harcourt Brace & Co

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1970. On Violence. San Diego, New York, and London: Harcourt Brace & Co

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1977. “Public Rights and Private Interests: In Response to Charles Frankel.” In Small Comforts for Hard Times: Humanists on Public Policy, eds. Michael J. Mooney and Florian Stuber. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1978a. The Life of the Mind. San Diego, New York, and London: Harcourt Brace & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1978b. The Jew as Pariah: Jewish Identity and Politics in the Modern Age, ed. Ron H. Feldman. New York: Grove Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1992. Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy, ed. Ronald Beiner. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1994. Essays in Understanding, 1930-1954, ed. Jerome Kohn. New York: Schocken Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1998. Love and Saint Augustine, ed. J. V. Scott and J. C. Stark. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 2003. Responsibility and Judgment, ed. and intro. Jerome Kohn. New York: Schocken Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 2004. The Origins of Totalitarianism, rev. edn. New York: Schocken Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 2007. The Jewish Writings, ed. Jerome Kohn and Ron H. Feldman. New York: Schocken Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah and Hans Jürgen Benedict. 2009. “Revolution, Violence, and Power: A Correspondence.” Constellations 16: 302-306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah and Karl Jaspers. 1992. Hannah Arendt/Karl Jaspers: Correspondence 1926-1969, eds. Lotte Kohler and Hans Saner, trans. Robert and Rita Kimber. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Augustine. 1998. Confessions, trans. Henry Chadwick. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Bauman, Zygmunt. 2004. Wasted Lives: Modernity and its Outcasts. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, Seyla. 2004. The Rights of Others: Aliens, Residents, and Citizens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, Richard J. 2002. Radical Evil: A Philosophical Interrogation. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, Richard J. 2005. The Abuse of Evil: The Corruption of Politics and Religion since 9/11. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, Richard J. 2008. “Are Arendt’s Reflections on Evil Still Relevant?” The Review of Politics 70: 64-76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blättler, Sidonia and Irene Marti. 2005. “Rosa Luxemburg and Hannah Arendt: Against the Destruction of Political Spheres of Freedom.” Hypatia 20: 88-101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Da Costa, Dia and Philip McMichael. 2007. “The Poverty of the Global Order.” Globalizations 4: 588-602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galtung, Johan. 1969. “Violence, Peace, and Peace Research.” Journal of Peace Research 6: 167-191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kateb, George. 1992. The Inner Ocean: Individualism and Democratic Culture. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kekes, John. 1990. Facing Evil. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, Richard H. and Dan Stone, eds. 2007. Hannah Arendt and the Uses of History: Imperialism, Nation, Race, and Genocide. New York: Berghahn Books.

  • Kohn, Jerome. 1996. “Evil and Plurality: Hannah Arendt’s Way to The Life of the Mind.” In Hannah Arendt: Twenty Years Later, eds. Larry May and Jerome Kohn. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lara, María Pía. 2007. Narrating Evil: A Postmetaphysical Theory of Reflective Judgment. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lines, Thomas. 2008. Making Poverty: A History. London and New York: Zed Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, Larry. 1996. “Socialization and Institutional Evil.” In Hannah Arendt: Twenty Years Later, eds. Larry May and Jerome Kohn. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • McCarthy, Thomas. 2009. Race, Empire, and the Idea of Human Development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nino, Carlos. 1996. Radical Evil on Trial. New Haven, CT and London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parekh, Serena. 2008. Hannah Arendt and the Challenge of Modernity: A Phenomenology of Human Rights. New York and London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitkin, Hanna Fenichel. 1981. “Justice: On Relating Private and Public.” Political Theory 9: 327-352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitkin, Hanna Fenichel. 1998. The Attack of the Blob: Hannah Arendt’s Concept of the Social. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, Thomas. 1998. “A Global Resources Dividend.” In Ethics of Consumption: The Good Life, Justice, and Global Stewardship, eds. David A. Crocker and Toby Linden. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

  • Pogge, Thomas. 2002. World Poverty and Human Rights. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, Thomas. 2005. “World Poverty and Human Rights.” Ethics & International Affairs 19: 1-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Somers, Margaret R. Genealogies of Citizenship: Markets, Statelessness, and the Right to Have Rights. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • United Nations Development Program. 1999. Human Development Report 1999. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • United Nations Development Program. 2007. Human Development Report 2005. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • United Nations High Commissioner for Refugees. 2006a. Global Trends 2006: Refugees, Asylum-seekers, Returnees, Internally Displaced and Stateless Persons. Available at http://www.unhcr.org/statistics/STATISTICS/4676a71d4.pdf. Accessed on 27 August 2009.

  • United Nations High Commissioner for Refugees. 2006b. “Refugees by Numbers 2006 Edition.” Available at http://www.unhcr.org/basics/BASICS/4523b0bb2.pdf. Accessed on 27 August 2009.

  • United Nations Programme on HIV/AIDS and World Health Organization. 2005. AIDS Epidemic Update 2005. Geneva: UNAIDS/WHO.

    Google Scholar 

  • Villa, Dana. 1999. Politics, Philosophy, Terror: Essays on the Thought of Hannah Arendt. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Villa, Dana. 2008. Public Freedom. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolin, Sheldon S. 1994. “Hannah Arendt: Democracy and the Political.” In Hannah Arendt: Critical Essays, eds. Lewis P. Hinchman and Sandra K. Hinchman. Albany: SUNY Press.

  • World Bank. 2004. Global Development Finance 2004. Washington, DC: The World Bank.

    Google Scholar 

  • World Health Organization. 2004. World Health Report 2004. Geneva: WHO.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young-Bruehl, Elisabeth. 2006. Why Arendt Matters. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Patrick Hayden.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Hayden, P. The Relevance of Hannah Arendt’s Reflections on Evil: Globalization and Rightlessness. Hum Rights Rev 11, 451–467 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12142-010-0157-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12142-010-0157-8

Keywords

Navigation