Skip to main content
Log in

Dimensions of integration in embedded and extended cognitive systems

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The complementary properties and functions of cognitive artifacts and other external resources are integrated into the human cognitive system to varying degrees. The goal of this paper is to develop some of the tools to conceptualize this complementary integration between agents and artifacts. It does so by proposing a multidimensional framework, including the dimensions of information flow, reliability, durability, trust, procedural transparency, informational transparency, individualization, and transformation. The proposed dimensions are all matters of degree and jointly they constitute a multidimensional space in which situated cognitive systems can be located and have certain dimensional configurations. These dimensions provide a new perspective on the conditions for cognitive extension. They are, however, not meant to provide a set of necessary and sufficient conditions, but to provide a toolbox for investigating the degree and nature of the integration of agent and artifact into “new systemic wholes”. The higher a situated system scores on the proposed dimensions, the more functional integration occurs, and the more tightly coupled the system is.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See also Clark’s (1997) “007 principle” and Mark Rowlands’ (1999) “Barking Dog principle”.

  2. A reviewer pointed out that, in some cases, using a cognitive artifact to perform some task does not always result in a more adaptable and powerful problem-solving system. For example, when the artifact provides too much information, making it hard to decide which information is relevant for performing the task, or when the information is not sufficiently transparent (see Section 3.6). So not all agent-artifact systems are necessarily more adaptable.

  3. For critical discussions of these conditions, see Rupert (2004), Rockwell (2010), Roberts (2011), Adams and Maher (2012), Palermos (2014), Smart (2012), Michaelian (2012), Halpin (2013), Arango-Muñoz (2013), and Ludwig (2014).

  4. The dimension of information flow is somewhat related to Sterelny’s (2010) dimension of individual versus collective use, but is more fine-grained.

  5. A reviewer pointed out that, whether a situated system should be classified as two-way or reciprocal, depends on how the artifact in question is used. For example, in case of a shopping list, it can be classified as a two-way system when its user writes down the needed items and then disposes the list when it is no longer needed. However, it can also be classified as a reciprocal system when its user changes the list while doing the shopping and, consequently, turning a shopping list into a more thorough tool for the next use.

  6. See also John Haugeland (1998) on bandwidth between two entities, and Clark’s (2007) discussion of Haugeland.

  7. See Clark (2008a) for similar ideas on multiple realizability in situated cognitive systems, and see Gallagher and Crisafi (2009) on socially distributed systems exhibiting different composition but with similar functions regarding legal decision-making.

  8. Although Clowes does not distinguish between procedural and representational transparency, I take it he is referring to procedural transparency, as he illustrates his point by making an analogy to Heidegger’s notion of a hammer being ready-to-hand.

  9. A reviewer pointed out that, in some cases, fast information-processing may not be desirable, as it runs the risk of superficiality and lack of understanding. In an educational context, for example, slow information-processing may be advantageous, as it increases understanding of a problem or concept.

  10. Sterelny (2010) presents a similar approach on a multidimensional space, but with only three dimensions.

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams, Z., & Maher, C. (2012). Cognitive spread: under what conditions does the mind extend beyond the body. European Journal of Philosophy. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0378.2012.00543.x.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arango-Muñoz, S. (2013). Scaffolded memory and metacognitive feelings. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4, 135–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arnau, E., Ayala, S., & Sturm, T. (2013). Cognitive externalism meets bounded rationality. In M. Knauff, M. Pauen, N. Sebanz, & I. Wachsmuth (Eds.), Proceedings of the 35th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 1768–1773).

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body and world back together again. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2001). Mindware: An introduction to the philosophy of cognitive science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2007). Reinventing ourselves: the plasticity of embodiment, sensing, and mind. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 32(3), 263–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008a). Pressing the flesh: a tension in the study of the embodied, embedded mind? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76(1), 37–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008b). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 10–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clowes, R. W. (2012). Hybrid memory, cognitive technology, and self. In J. M. Bishop & Y. J. Erden (Eds.), Proceedings of the 5th AISB Symposium on Computing and Philosophy (pp. 4–13).

  • Clowes, R. W. (2013). The cognitive integration of e-memory. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4(1), 107–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Cruz, H. (2008). An extended mind perspective on natural number representation. Philosophical Psychology, 21(4), 475–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S. (2004). Evolution of human cortical circuits for reading and arithmetic: The neuronal recycling hypothesis. In S. Dehaene, M. D. Hauser, & G. Rizzolatti (Eds.), From monkey brain to human brain (pp. 133–157). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., Spelke, E., Pinel, P., Stanescu, R., & Tsivkin, S. (1999). Sources of mathematical thinking: behavioral and brain imaging evidence. Science, 284, 970–974.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Crisafi, A. (2009). Mental institutions. Topoi, 28, 45–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenwood, J. (2013a). Contingent transcranialism and deep functional cognitive integration: the case of human emotional ontogenesis. Philosophical Psychology, 26(3), 420–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenwood, J. (2013b). Is mind extended or scaffolded? Ruminations on Sterelney’s (2010) extended stomach. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. doi:10.1007/s11097-013-9337-8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halpin, H. (2013). Does the web extend the mind? In Proceedings of the 5th annual ACM web science conference (pp. 139–147).

  • Haugeland, J. (1998). Mind embodied and embedded. In Having thought: Essays in the metaphysics of mind (pp. 207–237). Harvard University Press.

  • Heersmink, R. (2012). Mind and artifact: A multidimensional matrix for exploring cognition-artifact relations. In J. M. Bishop & Y. J. Erden (Eds.), Proceedings of the 5th AISB Symposium on Computing and Philosophy (pp. 54–61).

  • Heersmink, R. (2013). A taxonomy of cognitive artifacts: function, information, and categories. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4(3), 465–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heersmink, R. (forthcoming). The metaphysics of cognitive artifacts. Philosophical Explorations.

  • Hutchins, E. (1995a). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. (1995b). How a cockpit remembers its speed. Cognitive Science, 19(3), 265–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, M. D. (2011). Extended cognition and fixed properties: steps to a third-wave version of extended cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11(2), 287–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh, D. (1995). The intelligent use of space. Artificial Intelligence, 72, 1–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh, D., & Maglio, P. (1994). On distinguishing epistemic from pragmatic action. Cognitive Science, 18, 513–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiverstein, J., & Farina, M. (2011). Embraining culture: leaky minds and spongy brains. Teorema, 32(2), 35–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loader, P. (2012). The epistemic/pragmatic distinction. Philosophical Explorations, 15(2), 219–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig, D. (2014). Extended cognition and the explosion of knowledge. Philosophical Psychology. doi:10.1080/09515089.2013.867319.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, P. D. (2009). On trusting wikipedia. Episteme, 6(1), 74–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2007). Cognitive integration: Mind and cognition unbounded. Basingstoke: Palgrave McMillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2010a). Dimensions of mind. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9(4), 561–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2010b). Cognitive integration and the extended mind. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 227–243). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R., & Kirchhoff, M. (2013). Cognitive transformations and extended expertise. Educational Philosophy and Theory. doi:10.1080/00131857.2013.779209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. (2012). Is external memory, memory? Biological memory and extended mind. Consciousness and Cognition, 21(3), 1154–1165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K., & Sutton, J. (2013). Distributed cognition and memory research: history and current directions. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N. J. (2005). Interpreting scientific and engineering practices: Integrating the cognitive, social, and cultural dimensions. In M. Gorman, R. Tweney, D. Gooding, & A. Kincannon (Eds.), New directions in scientific and technical thinking (pp. 17–56). Mahwah: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N. J. (2006). The cognitive-cultural systems of the research laboratory. Organization Studies, 27(1), 125–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norman, D. (1993). Things that make us smart: Defending human attributes in the age of the machine. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palermos, S. O. (2014). Loops, constitution, and cognitive extension. Cognitive Systems Research, 27, 25–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parsell, M. (2007). The cognitive cost of extending an evolutionary mind into the environment. Cognitive Processing, 7, 3–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pierce, C. S. (1935). The collected papers of Charles S. Pierce vol 2. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preston, B. (2009). Philosophical theories of artifact function. In A. Meijers (Ed.), Philosophy of technology and engineering sciences (pp. 213–234). The Netherlands: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Preston, B. (2013). A philosophy of material culture: Action, function, and mind. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, T. (2011). Taking responsibility for cognitive extension. Philosophical Psychology, 25(4), 491–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rockwell, T. (2010). Extended cognition and intrinsic properties. Philosophical Psychology, 23(6), 741–757.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind: Understanding cognitive processes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2010). The new science of the mind: From extended mind to embodied phenomenology. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 101(8), 389–428.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, J. (2013). Trust. In D. Pritchard (Ed.), Oxford bibliographies in philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, P. (2012). The web-extended mind. Metaphilosophy, 43(4), 446–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2004). Externalism, epistemic artefacts and the extended mind. In R. Schantz (Ed.), The externalist challenge. New studies on cognition and intentionality (pp. 239–254). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2010). Minds: extended or scaffolded? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9(4), 465–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (2006). Distributed cognition: domains and dimensions. Pragmatics and Cognition, 14(2), 235–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (2008). Material agency, skills and history: Distributed cognition and the archaeology of memory. In C. Knappet & L. Malafouris (Eds.), Material agency (pp. 37–55). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (2009a). The feel of the world: Exograms, habits, and the confusion of types of memory. In A. Kania (Ed.), Philosophers on memento (pp. 65–86). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (2009b). Remembering. In P. Robbins & M. Aydede (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of situated cognition (pp. 217–235). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (2010). Exograms and interdisciplinarity: History, the extended mind and the civilizing process. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 189–225). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J., Harris, C. B., Keil, P., & Barnier, A. J. (2010). The psychology of memory, extended cognition, and socially distributed remembering. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9, 521–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Theiner, G. (2013). Transactive memory systems: a mechanistic analysis of emergent group memory. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4(1), 65–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tollefson, D., Dale, R., & Paxton, A. (2013). Alignment, transactive memory, and collective cognitive systems. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4(1), 49–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tribble, E. (2011). Cognition in the globe: Attention and memory in Shakespeare’s theatre. Houndmills: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, B., & Suwa, M. (2009). Thinking with sketches. In A. Markman (Ed.), Tools for innovation (pp. 75–84). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Vorms, M. (2012). Formats of representation in scientific theorising. In P. Humphreys & C. Imbert (Eds.), Models, simulations, and representations (pp. 250–273). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walter, S. (2010). Cognitive extension: the parity argument, functionalism, and the mark of the cognitive. Synthese, 177, 285–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2010). In defence of extended functionalism. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 245–270). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2011). In search of clarity about parity. Philosophical Studies, 152, 417–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (2004). Boundaries of mind: The individual in the fragile sciences. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R., & Clark, A. (2009). How to situate cognition: Letting nature take its course. In P. Robbins & M. Aydede (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of situated cognition (pp. 55–77). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woelert, P. (2012). Idealization and external symbolic storage: the epistemic and technical dimensions of theoretic cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11, 335–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, J. (1997). The nature of external representations in problem solving. Cognitive Science, 21(2), 179–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to express my gratitude to John Sutton and Richard Menary for helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper. I would also like to thank the audiences at the Distributed Cognition and Distributed Agency Workshop (Sydney, 2012) and the AISB/IACAP World Congress (Birmingham, 2012) for useful feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Richard Heersmink.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Heersmink, R. Dimensions of integration in embedded and extended cognitive systems. Phenom Cogn Sci 14, 577–598 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-014-9355-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-014-9355-1

Keywords

Navigation