Skip to main content
Log in

Deontology defended

  • S.I.: Neuroscience and Its Philosophy
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Empirical research into moral decision-making is often taken to have normative implications. For instance, in his recent book, Greene (2013) relies on empirical findings to establish utilitarianism as a superior normative ethical theory. Kantian ethics, and deontological ethics more generally, is a rival view that Greene attacks. At the heart of Greene’s argument against deontology is the claim that deontological moral judgments are the product of certain emotions and not of reason. Deontological ethics is a mere rationalization of these emotions. Accordingly Greene maintains that deontology should be abandoned. This paper is a defense of deontological ethical theory. It argues that Greene’s argument against deontology needs further support. Greene’s empirical evidence is open to alternative interpretations. In particular, it is not clear that Greene’s characterization of alarm-like emotions that are relative to culture and personal experience is empirically tenable. Moreover, it is implausible that such emotions produce specifically deontological judgments. A rival sentimentalist view, according to which all moral judgments are determined by emotion, is at least as plausible given the empirical evidence and independently supported by philosophical theory. I therefore call for an improvement of Greene’s argument.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The switch case was first introduced by Foot (1978), the footbridge case by Thomson (1985).

  2. Functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) is a species of scientific neuroimaging. It implicitly assumes that active brain regions consume a comparatively high amount of oxygen, causing a change in blood flow, which in turn can be visualised through magnetic fields.

  3. Greene's initial hypothesis was that the two classes of dilemmas could be distinguished by whether they were ‘personal’ or ‘impersonal’. A personal dilemma leads to serious bodily harm of a particular person in such a way that it is not a result of deflecting a threat onto a third party (Greene and Haidt 2002, p. 519). An impersonal dilemma does not involve such a harm. However, the personal-impersonal distinction has been criticized by various authors (e.g., Nichols and Mallon 2006; Mikhail 2007) and finally been questioned by Greene himself (Greene 2007b, p. 108).

  4. Ironically, the utilitarian Jeremy Bentham seems to have been one of the first philosophers to use ‘deontology’ (Louden 1996, pp. 573–579). He applied it far more broadly than we do nowadays, sometimes as a synonym for ‘ethics’, sometimes as a synonym for ‘utilitarianism’.

  5. Greene would claim that, by targeting the former, he also refutes the latter. Whether this claim is correct is a question that has been addressed elsewhere.

  6. This argument is most developed in Greene (2007a), an earlier paper to which Greene refers in his book (Greene 2013, p. 381) for further detail.

  7. I thank an anonymous reviewer for clarificatory advice.

  8. I thank an anonymous reviewer for Synthese for helping me see this implication.

  9. A view on which the strength to which emotions influence a moral judgment determines its normative status would also have to explain how relativity to culture or personal experience should determine this influence on moral judgment. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for this point.

  10. There are others but I do not have the space to discuss them here. For instance, Nichols and Mallon (2006) take the view that moral decision-making is determined by rule-based assessments, regardless of whether these rules concern consequentialist or deontological considerations. Rules are supplemented by emotion and cost–benefit analysis.

  11. I thank an anonymous reviewer for Synthese for bringing the relevance of this literature to my attention.

  12. Strawson laments that “it is a pity that talk of the moral sentiments has fallen out of favour” (2008 [1960], p. 26), as he regards it as quite apt to describe reactive attitudes.

  13. I thank an anonymous reviewer for suggesting this objection and reply.

References

  • American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (5th ed.). Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Association.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, S., Bechara, A., Damasio, H., Tranel, D., & Damasio, A. (1999). Impairment of social and moral behavior related to early damage in human prefrontal cortex. Nature Neuroscience, 2(11), 1032.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartels, D., & Pizarro, D. (2011). The mismeasure of morals: Antisocial personality traits predict utilitarian responses to moral dilemmas. Cognition, 121(1), 154–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechara, A., Damasio, H., Tranel, D., & Damasio, A. (1997). Deciding advantageously before knowing the advantageous strategy. Science, 275, 1293–1295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berker, S. (2009). The normative insignificance of neuroscience. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 37(4), 293–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blair, J., Mitchell, D., & Blair, K. (2005). The psychopath: Emotion and the brain. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bossaerts, P. (2009). What decision neuroscience teaches us about financial decision making. Annual Review of Financial Economics, 1(1), 383–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ciaramelli, E., Muccioli, M., Làdavas, E., & di Pellegrino, G. (2007). Selective deficit in personal moral judgment following damage to ventromedial prefrontal cortex. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 2(2), 84–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Côté, S., Piff, P., & Willer, R. (2013). For whom do the ends justify the means? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 104(3), 490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crockett, M., Clark, L., Hauser, M., & Robbins, T. (2010). Serotonin selectively influences moral judgment and behavior through effects on harm aversion. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 107(40), 17433–17438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, E., & Gächter, S. (2002). Altruistic punishment in humans. Nature, 415(6868), 137–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fellows, L., & Farah, M. (2007). The role of ventromedial prefrontal cortex in decision making. Cerebral Cortex, 17(11), 2669–2674.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (1978). Virtues and vices. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R. (1988). Passions within reason: The strategic role of the emotions. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, M., & Le Doux, J. (1978). The integrated mind. New York: Plenum.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise choices, apt feelings. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gill, M., & Nichols, S. (2008). Sentimentalist pluralism: Moral psychology and philosophical ethics. Philosophical Issues, 18, 143–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glimcher, P., & Fehr, E. (Eds.). (2013). Neuroeconomics: Decision making and the brain. London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, J., Nosek, B., Haidt, J., Iyer, R., Koleva, S., & Ditto, P. (2011). Mapping the moral domain. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 101, 366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2007a). The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology, volume 3: The neuroscience of morality (pp. 35–79). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2007b). Reply to Mikhail and Timmons. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology, volume 3: The neuroscience of morality (pp. 105–117). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. http://www.wjh.harvard.edu/jgreene/GreeneWJH/Greene-KantSoul.pdf. Accessed 26 Jan 2010.

  • Greene, J. (2007c). Why are VMPFC patients more utilitarian? A dual-process theory of moral judgment explains. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11(8), 322–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2013). Moral tribes. London: Atlantic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2014). Beyond point-and-shoot morality: Why cognitive (neuro) science matters for ethics. Ethics, 124(4), 695–726.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J., & Haidt, J. (2002). How (and where) does moral judgment work? Trends in Cognitive Science, 6, 517–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J., Morelli, S., Lowenberg, K., Nystrom, L., & Cohen, J. (2008). Cognitive load selectively interferes with utilitarian moral judgment. Cognition, 107, 1144–1154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J., Nystrom, L., Engell, A., Darlez, J., & Cohen, J. (2004). The neural bases of cognitive conflict and control in moral judgment. Neuron, 44, 389–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J., Sommerville, R., Nystrom, L., Darley, J., & Cohen, J. (2001). An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science, 293, 2105–2108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, 814–834.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics. Daedalus, 133(4), 55–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J., Koller, S., & Dias, M. (1993). Affect, culture, and morality, or is it wrong to eat your dog? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65, 613–628.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1978 [1739/40]). A treatise of human nautre. L. A. Selby/Bigge & P. H. Nidditch (Eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Hume, D. (1998 [1751]). An Enquiry concerning the principles of morals. T. L. Beauchamp (Ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Hutcherson, C., Montaser-Kouhsari, L., Woodward, J., & Rangel, A. (2015). Emotional and utilitarian appraisals of moral dilemmas are encoded in separate areas and integrated in ventromedial prefrontal cortex. Journal of Neuroscience, 35(36), 12593–12605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutcheson, F. (2002 [1728]), An essay on the nature and conduct of passions, with illustrations on the moral sense. A. Garrett (Ed.). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Hutcheson, F. (2004 [1725]). An inquiry into the original of our ideas of beauty and virtue in two treatises. W. Leidhold (Ed.). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Kahane, G. (2011). Evolutionary debunking arguments. Noûs, 45(1), 103–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G. (2014). Intuitive and counterintuitive morality. In J. D’Arms & D. Jacobsen (Eds.), The science of ethics: Moral psychology and human agency (pp. 9–39). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G., & Shackel, N. (2010). Methodological issues in the neuroscience of moral judgement. Mind and Language, 25(5), 561–582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G., Wiech, K., Shackel, N., Farias, M., Savulescu, J., & Tracey, I. (2011). The neural basis of intuitive and counterintuitive moral judgment. Social cognitive and affective neuroscience, 7(4), 393–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, F. (1999). Nonconsequentialism. In H. LaFollette (Ed.), The Blackwell guide to ethical theory. Oxford: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, F. (2009). Neuroscience and moral reasoning: A note on recent research. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 37(4), 330–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1968). Werke. Berlin: De Gruyter (Original work published in 1902).

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, C. (2010). Philosophical issues in neuroimaging. Philosophy Compass, 5(2), 186–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, C. (2011). The dual track theory of moral decision-making: A critique of the neuroimaging evidence. Neuroethics, 4(2), 143–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koenigs, M., & Tranel, D. (2007). Irrational economic decision-making after ventromedial prefrontal damage: Evidence from the Ultimatum Game. Journal of Neuroscience, 27(4), 951–956.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koenigs, M., Young, L., Adolphs, R., Tranel, D., Cushman, F., Hauser, M., et al. (2007). Damage to the prefrontal cortex increases utilitarian moral judgements. Nature, 446(7138), 908.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liao, S. (2011). Bias and reasoning: Haidt’s theory of moral judgment. In T. Brooks (Ed.), New waves in ethics (pp. 108–128). London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Liao, S. (2016). Morality and neuroscience. In S. Liao (Ed.), Moral brains (pp. 1–42). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Liao, S., Wiegmann, A., Alexander, J., & Vong, G. (2012). Putting the trolley in order: Experimental philosophy and the loop case. Philosophical Psychology, 25(5), 661–671.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G. (2000). Emotions in economic theory and economic behavior. The American Economic Review, 90(2), 426–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Louden, R. (1996). Towards a genealogy of ‘deontology’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 34, 571–592.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mikhail, J. (2007). Moral cognition and computational theory. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology (pp. 81–91). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mogensen, A. (2015). Evolutionary debunking arguments and the proximate/ultimate distinction. Analysis, 75(2), 196–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moll, J., & de Oliveira-Souza, R. (2007). Response to Greene: Moral sentiments and reason: Friends or foes? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11(8), 323–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moll, J., Krueger, F., Zahn, R., Pardini, M., de Oliveira-Souza, R., & Grafman, J. (2006). Human fronto–mesolimbic networks guide decisions about charitable donation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 103(42), 15623–15628.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moll, J., Oliveira-Souza, R., Garrido, G., Bramati, I., Caparelli-Daquer, E., Paiva, M., et al. (2007). The self as a moral agent: Linking the neural bases of social agency and moral sensitivity. Social Neuroscience, 2(3–4), 336–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moll, J., Zahn, R., de Oliveira-Souza, R., Krueger, F., & Grafman, J. (2005). Opinion: The neural basis of human moral cognition. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 6(10), 799.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Mallon, R. (2006). Moral dilemmas and moral rules. Cognition, 100, 530–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicolle, A., & Goel, V. (2013). What is the role of ventromedial prefrontal cortex in emotional influences on reason? In I. Blanchette (Ed.), Emotion and reasoning (p. 154). Hove: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nordgren, L., & McDonnell, M. (2011). The scope-severity paradox: Why doing more harm is judged to be less harmful. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 2, 97–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, A., & Phelps, E. (2004). Learned fear of “unseen” faces after Pavlovian, observational, and instructed fear. Psychological Science, 15(12), 822–828.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, A., & Phelps, E. (2007). Social learning of fear. Nature Neuroscience, 10(9), 1095.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paxton, J., Bruni, T., & Greene, J. (2013). Are ‘counter-intuitive’ deontological judgments really counter-intuitive? An empirical reply to Kahane et al. (2012). Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 9(9), 1368–1371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2007). The emotional construction of morals. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2016). Sentimentalism and the moral brain. In M. Liao (Ed.), Moral brains: The neuroscience of morality (pp. 45–73). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rand, D., Greene, J., & Nowak, M. (2012). Spontaneous giving and calculated greed. Nature, 489(7416), 427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rozin, P., Lowery, L., Imada, S., & Haidt, J. (1999). The CAD triad hypothesis: A mapping between three moral emotions (contempt, anger, disgust) and three moral codes (community, autonomy, divinity). Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 76(4), 574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sanfey, A., Rilling, J., Aronson, J., Nystrom, L., & Cohen, J. (2003). The neural basis of economic decision-making in the ultimatum game. Science, 300(5626), 1755–1758.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. (1968). The life you save may be your own. In S. Chase (Ed.), Problems in public expenditure analysis (pp. 127–176). Washington: Brookings Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaftesbury, Third Earl of (2001 [1714]). An inquiry into virtue and merit. In D. Den Uyl (Ed.), Characteristicks of men, manners, opinions, times (Vol. 2, pp. 1–100). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Shenhav, A., & Greene, J. (2014). Integrative moral judgment: Dissociating the roles of the amygdala and ventromedial prefrontal cortex. Journal of Neuroscience, 34(13), 4741–4749.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, D. (2007). Moral address, moral responsibility, and the boundaries of the moral community. Ethics, 118(1), 70–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, D. (2011). Attributability, answerability, and accountability: Toward a wider theory of moral responsibility. Ethics, 121(3), 602–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shweder, R., Much, N., Mahapatra, M., & Park, L. (1997). The “big three” of morality (autonomy, community and divinity) and the “big three” explanations of suffering. In A. Brandt & P. Rozin (Eds.), Morality and health (pp. 119–169). Oxford: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1972). Famine, affluence, and morality. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 1, 229–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Small, D., & Loewenstein, G. (2003). Helping a victim or helping the victim: Altruism and identifiability. The Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 26, 5–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich, K., & West, R. (2000). Individual differences in reasoning: Implications for the rationality debate. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23, 645–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. (2008 [1960]). Freedom and resentment. In his Freedom and resentment and other essays (pp. 1–28). London: Routledge.

  • Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tabibnia, G., Satpute, A., & Lieberman, M. (2008). The sunny side of fairness: preference for fairness activates reward circuitry (and disregarding unfairness activates self-control circuitry). Psychological Science, 19(4), 339–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. (1985). The trolley problem. The Yale Law Journal, 94(6), 1395–1415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tricomi, E., Rangel, A., Camerer, C. & O’Doherty, J. (2010). Neural evidence for inequality-averse social preferences. Nature, 463(7284), 1089.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. (1996). Living high and letting die: Our illusion of innocence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wheatley, T., & Haidt, J. (2005). Hypnotic disgust makes moral judgments more severe. Psychological Science, 16(10), 780–784.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, L., Koenigs, M., Kruepke, M., & Newman, J. (2012). Psychopathy increases perceived moral permissibility of accidents. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 121(3), 659.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper has greatly benefitted from discussions with Gunnar Björnsson, Josh Greene, Richard Holton, Gina Rini, and audiences in Riga, Granada, and Mainz, as well as from a debate between Rae Langton and Joshua Greene in Cambridge. I also thank two anonymous reviewers for their extremely helpful feedback, which has to a great degree shaped and improved this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nora Heinzelmann.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Heinzelmann, N. Deontology defended. Synthese 195, 5197–5216 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1762-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1762-3

Keywords

Navigation