Skip to main content
Log in

A Feminist Critique of Justifications for Sex Selection

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Journal of Bioethical Inquiry Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper examines dominant arguments advocating for the procreative right to undergo sex selection for social reasons, based on gender preference. I present four of the most recognized and common justifications for sex selection: the argument from natural sex selection, the argument from procreative autonomy, the argument from family balancing, and the argument from children’s well-being. Together these represent the various means by which scholars aim to defend access to sex selection for social reasons as a legitimate procreative choice. In response, I contend that these justifications are flawed and often inconsistent and therefore fail to vindicate the practice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Some United Nations sources provide estimates of up to 200 million missing women (United Nations 2007).

  2. For example, Bernard Dickens (2002, 335) claims: “The urge to select children’s sex is not new. The Babylonian Talmud, a Jewish text completed towards the end of the fifth century of the Christian era, advises couples on means to favour the birth of either a male or a female child.” Interestingly, advocates of sex selection based on gender preference argue that the practice is ethically permissible in the West precisely because gender equality exists in the region. However, some such as Dickens build the legitimacy of the desire for a gender-specified child on the grounds of its roots in antiquity, with reference to ancient patriarchal societies. This is rather inconsistent.

  3. However, while advocates for sex selection in the West claim that women’s rights are violated in non-Western regions, they imply that the social impact of the deliberate large-scale selection against female children may not be strictly negative. On the contrary, some claim that skewed sex ratios can indeed have positive implications for the society. According to Sureau (1999, 868), “These could include: an increase in the influence and responsibilities of the gender which had become rare; a slowdown in the rate of growth of the world population, and reinforcement of the interbreeding of different populations due to the preferences indicated above, with beneficial consequences from both social and medical points of view.” This view is supported by Savulescu (2006, 148), who claims that skewed sex ratios may not be a negative thing, and that “even in Asia, it is not clear that sex selection should be banned.“ Thus, even scholars who acknowledge that large-scale sex selection against female children on sexist grounds has the capacity to reinforce discrimination against women (Sureau 1999; Savulescu 2001), justify the practice.

  4. Berkowitz and Snyder (1998) reflect on this aspect in their understanding of sexism. They argue: “Sexism is a consequence of assumed sex appropriate social roles, social roles which are of human invention and not genetically determined. For example, one would be hard pressed to call sexist the situation where only woman can bear children: an irrevocable result of natural law. It would, however, be sexist to assume that women are superior to men at child rearing as this assumes that women are better suited for a particular social task” (31).

  5. Similarly, Pennings (1996, 2342) argues that the wish to have children of “both sexes” is not biased but rather a sign of “appreciation of sexual differences.” Following this line of argument, he claims: “in a society where there would be absolutely no discrimination on the basis of sex, there will still be parents who wish to have a child of a specific sex” (2342). Clearly, on his account, gender preference is based on real existing differences, which in turn justifies sex selection. However, this is a highly hypothetical argument—there is no way to prove this claim, as we have no experience with such a social order.

  6. Recent studies in neuroscience challenge the belief that “the sexes cluster distinctively and consistently at opposite ends of a single gender continuum” (Rippon et al. 2014, 3) or have distinctively feminine and masculine traits (Fine 2010; Fine et al. 2013). Instead, they suggest that all humans tend to express “feminine” and “masculine” characteristics and behaviours. These characteristics are expressed in complex ways and scales not in terms of a categorical two-dimensional gender difference. Hence, there are no two distinctively male and female personalities.

  7. These gender stereotypical expectations were captured in a recent study with Australian women who have selected or desired to select for daughters. For example, one participant explained that she desired a daughter because she wanted a close mother–child bond: “My boys are still little, but my perception is that you don’t have that same [kind of relationship with] boys … Boys grow up and fly the coop and make their own lives, have their own families kind of thing, whereas girls, my perception, is that they stay a little bit more closely aligned with their family. Girls are more family oriented than boys necessarily” (Hendl Forthcoming, n.p.). Another participant explained: “I love the boys, but I just thought it would be nice to have a daughter. It’s nice—you go shopping, and you get a bit sick of blue and red and orange and brown. Well, I just thought it would be nice to get some pink in the house” (Hendl Forthcoming, n.p.). These quotes suggest that at least some of the parents who want to conceive a female child and invest in the process of sex selection, have a particular type of girl in mind; a girl who will conform to stereotypical expectations about feminine traits, looks, and behaviour.

References

  • Bayles, M.D. 1990. Genetic choice. In Ethical issues in the new reproductive technologies, edited by R.T. Hull, 241–258. Belmont: Wadsworth Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkowitz, J.M., and J.W. Snyder. 1998. Racism and sexism in medically assisted conception. Bioethics 12(1): 25–44.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bhatia, R. 2010. Constructing gender from the inside out: Sex-selection practices in the United States. Feminist Studies 36(2): 260–291.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birdsall, M.L. 2010. An exploration of “the ‘Wild West’ of reproductive technology”: Ethical and feminist perspectives on sex-selection practices in the United States. William & Mary Journal of Women and the Law 17(1): 223–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bongaarts, J., and C.Z. Guilmoto. 2015. How many more missing women? Excess female mortality and prenatal sex selection, 1970–2050. Population and Development Review, 41(2): 241–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Browne, T.K. 2017. How sex selection undermines reproductive autonomy. Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 14(2). Doi. 10.1007/s11673-017-9783-z.

  • Butler, J. 1990. Gender trouble: Feminism and the subversion of identity. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Council of Europe. 2011. Resolution 1829: Prenatal Sex Selection. Strasbourg: Council of Europe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darnovsky, M. 2003. Sex selection moves to the consumer culture—Ads for “family balancing“ in the New York Times. Genetics and Society, August 20. https://www.geneticsandsociety.org/article/sex-selection-moves-consumer-culture. Accessed May 11, 2016.

  • ———. n.d. Revisiting sex selection. https://pol285.blog.gustavus.edu/files/2009/08/Darnovsky_Revisiting_Sex_Selection.pdf. Accessed June 28, 2017.

  • Davis, G., J.M. Dewey, and E.L. Murphy. 2016. Giving sex: Deconstructing intersex and trans medicalization practices. Gender & Society 30(3): 490–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Wert, G., and W. Dondorp. 2010. Preconception sex selection for non-medical and intermediate reasons: Ethical reflections. Facts, Views and Vision in Obstetrics and Gynaecology 2(4): 80–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickens, B.M. 2002. Can sex selection be ethically tolerated? Journal of Medical Ethics 28(6): 335–336.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Fausto-Sterling, A. 1993. The five sexes. The Sciences 33(2): 20–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Sexing the body: Gender politics and the construction of sexuality. New York: Basic Books.

  • Fine, C. 2010. Delusions of gender. London: Icon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, C., R. Jordan-Young, A. Kaiser, and G. Rippon. 2013. Plasticity, plasticity, plasticity ... and the rigid problem of sex. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 17(11): 550–551.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Fuse, K. 2013. Daughter preference in Japan: A reflection on gender role attitudes? Demographic Research 28: 36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M.A. 2009. Defeating bigenderism: Changing gender assumptions in the twenty-first century. Hypatia 24(3): 93–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. 2003. The future of human nature. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. 1992. Wonderwoman and Superman. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Sex selection and regulated hatred. Journal of Medical Ethics 31(5): 291–294.

  • Hendl, T. Forthcoming. Queering the odds. The case against “family balancing.” International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 10(2).

  • Holm, S. 2004. Like a frog in boiling water: The public, the HFEA and sex selection. Health Care Analysis 12(1): 27–39.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, C. 2015. Autonomy. In Routledge companion to bioethics, edited by J. Arras, E. Fenton, and R. Kukla, 277–289. New York & London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcus, L., K. Marcus, S.M. Yaxte, and K. Marcus. 2015. Genderqueer: One family’s experience with gender variance. Psychoanalytic Inquiry 35(8): 795–808.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDougall, R. 2005. Acting parentally: An argument against sex selection. Journal of Medical Ethics 31(10): 601–605.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Parental virtue: A new way of thinking about the morality of reproductive actions. Bioethics 21(4): 181–190.

  • Mudde, A. 2010. “Before you formed in the womb I knew you”: Sex selection and spaces of ambiguity. Hypatia 25(3): 553–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • National Health and Medical Research Council. 2014. Review of Part B of the Ethical guidelines for the use of assisted reproductive technology in clinical practice and research, 2007. http://consultations.nhmrc.gov.au/public_consultations/assisted_reproductive. Accessed May 10, 2017.

  • Pennings, G. 1996. Ethics of sex selection for family balancing. Human Reproduction 11(1993): 2339–2343.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Puri, S., V. Adams, S. Ivey, and R.D. Nachtigall. 2011. “There is such a thing as too many daughters, but not too many sons”: A qualitative study of son preference and fetal sex selection among Indian immigrants in the United States. Social Science & Medicine 72(7): 1169–1176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rippon, G., R. Jordan-Young, A. Kaiser, and C. Fine. 2014. Recommendations for sex gender neuroimaging research: Key principles and implications for research design, analysis, and interpretation. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8: 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, J. 1996. Children of choice. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. Preconception sex selection. American Journal of Bioethics 1(1): 2–9.

  • Rothman, B. Katz. 1998. Genetic maps and human imaginations: The limits of science in understanding who we are. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothschild, J. 2005. The dream of the perfect child. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryan, M. 1990. The argument for unlimited procreative liberty: A feminist critique. Hastings Center Report 20(4): 6–12.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkaria, M. K. 2009. Lessons from Punjab’s “missing girls”: Toward a global feminist perspective on “choice” in abortion. California Law Review 97: 905–942.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J. 2001. Procreative beneficence: Why we should select the best children. Bioethics 15(5–6): 336–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006. Sex selection: The case for. In Bioethics: An anthology, edited by H. Kuhse, and P. Singer, 145–149. Malden, MA: Balckwell.

  • Savulescu, J., and E. Dahl. 2000. Sex selection and preimplantation diagnosis. A response to the ethics committee of the American Society of Reproductive Medicine. Human Reproduction 15(9): 1879–1880.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Seavilleklein, V., and S. Sherwin. 2007. The myth of the gendered chromosome: Sex selection and the social interest. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 16(1): 7–19.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Segal, T.M. 2010. The role of the reproductive technology clinic in the imposition of societal values. International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 3(2): 90–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. 2003. Missing women—revisited. British Medical Journal 327(7427): 1297–1298.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Sherwin, S. 2007. Genetic enhancement, sports and relational autonomy. Sports, Ethics and Philosophy 1(2): 171–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strange, H., and R. Chadwick. 2010. The ethics of nonmedical sex selection. Health Care Analysis 18(3): 252–266.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Stryker, S. 2008. Transgender history. Berkeley: Seal Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sureau, C. 1999. Sex selection: A crime against humanity or the exercise of a fundamental right? Human Reproduction 14(4): 867–872.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • The Fertility Institutes. 2014. Sex selection. http://www.fertility-docs.com/programs-and-services/gender-selection/select-the-gender-of-your-baby-using-pgd.php. Accessed May 9, 2016.

  • Tonkens, R. 2011. Parental wisdom, empirical blindness, and normative evaluation of prenatal genetic enhancement. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 36(3): 274–295.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • United Nations. 2007. International women’s day 2007: Take action to end impunity for violence against women and girls. http://www.un.org/events/women/iwd/2007/factsfigures.shtml. Accessed October 13, 2016.

  • United Nations Development Programme. 2010. Human development report 2010. New York: United Nations Development Programme.

    Google Scholar 

  • United Nations Population Fund. 2012. Sex imbalances at birth. http://www.unfpa.org/sites/default/files/pub-pdf/Sex%20Imbalances%20at%20Birth.%20PDF%20UNFPA%20APRO%20publication%202012.pdf. Accessed June 7, 2017.

  • Wertz, D.C., and J.C. Fletcher. 1992. Sex selection through prenatal diagnosis: A feminist critique. In Feminist perspectives in medical ethics, edited by H. Bequaert Holmes and L.M. Purdy, 240–253. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, S. 2010. Choosing tomorrow’s children. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, S., and E. Garrard. 2013. Sex selection. https://www.keele.ac.uk/media/keeleuniversity/ri/risocsci/eugenics2013/Sex%20Selection%20Low%20Res.pdf. Accessed May 7, 2016.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tereza Hendl.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hendl, T. A Feminist Critique of Justifications for Sex Selection. Bioethical Inquiry 14, 427–438 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-017-9797-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11673-017-9797-6

Keywords

Navigation