Skip to main content
Log in

Non-separability Does Not Relieve the Problem of Bell’s Theorem

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper addresses arguments that “separability” is an assumption of Bell’s theorem, and that abandoning this assumption in our interpretation of quantum mechanics (a position sometimes referred to as “holism”) will allow us to restore a satisfying locality principle. Separability here means that all events associated to the union of some set of disjoint regions are combinations of events associated to each region taken separately.

In this article, it is shown that: (a) localised events can be consistently defined without implying separability; (b) the definition of Bell’s locality condition does not rely on separability in any way; (c) the proof of Bell’s theorem does not use separability as an assumption. If, inspired by considerations of non-separability, the assumptions of Bell’s theorem are weakened, what remains no longer embodies the locality principle. Teller’s argument for “relational holism” and Howard’s arguments concerning separability are criticised in the light of these results. Howard’s claim that Einstein grounded his arguments on the incompleteness of QM with a separability assumption is also challenged. Instead, Einstein is better interpreted as referring merely to the existence of localised events. Finally, it is argued that Bell rejected the idea that separability is an assumption of his theorem.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Maudlin has coined the term “The Fallacy of the Unnecessary Adjective” to indicate this problem with descriptions of Bell’s theorem [15], citing “realistic,” “hidden-variable” and “counterfactually definite” as examples of unnecessary adjectives that have cropped up between “local” and “theories”.

  2. Healy compares definitions of separability in which physical processes supervene on properties defined at points and/or arbitrarily small neighbourhoods of those points ([27], p. 46). See also [28] for a related discussion. The main conclusions of this article are independent of this distinction.

  3. This last point derives from comments made by Spekkens in a seminar [33].

  4. Spekkens later endorsed an different view, however, arguing that Bell’s theorem does not rely on separability [33, 34].

  5. As will become clear, “correlation” here takes on a specific meaning: a lack of statistical independence of the events given a probability distribution, i.e. in an obvious notation, P(A)P(B)≠P(AB). This is distinct from definitions by which the actual occurrence of two events implies a correlation between them, as discussed in the present context in [4]. In line with this, “event” has the meaning it does in the theory of stochastic processes and e.g. [28], that is, it is a proposition that may or may not be true in any possible realisation (or “history”) of the process, and to which is associated a probability (or probabilities). That is, the definition of correlation employed here does not refer to actual particular happenings such as the fact that a particular coin flip produced “heads”, but the theoretically given probabilities of such results.

  6. Conditions of this type, with these different past regions, are shown to be equivalent in a similar framework in [36] (for some debate on whether the proof is sound, see [38, 39]). However, the proof employed separability, called rule (iv) there.

  7. The are a number of choices in how to present the experiment. Here I select the “big history space approach” [28] that includes A s and B s as events with probabilities of their own, rather than having to deal with the complication of treating them as parameters of a family of probability distributions which are nevertheless localised. These doubtful probabilities could be removed without harming the argument in its essentials, as usual. The experimental probabilities μ(a o b o |a s b s ) do not depend on the absolute probabilities of the settings.

  8. This may not be so realistic; in a more general treatment, we might allow settings to correlate to some set of past events in the model which nonetheless were independent of every other event of relevance, or even allow limited correlations using some “careful epsilonics” as Bell puts it ([1] 1977 p. 102). Another way to represent the same situation would be to replace the requirement that λ be a “full specification” with the requirement that it has “sufficient completeness for a certain accuracy”, as Bell explains ([1] 1977 p. 104). See [6, 40] for more on this. In any case, the main point of this article does not turn on the issues.

  9. Healey once convincingly argued that a non-separable event in a region \(\mathcal {A}\cup \mathcal {B}\) could be influenced by events to its past without violating “relativistic locality” [21]. However, the conclusion that “there is no sound reason” to say that his interactive interpretation [18] of the EPRB experiment “violates any defensible relativistic locality condition” ([21], p. 369) is unwarranted. The argument above shows that it must violate one: the very condition that causes all the fuss about quantum non-locality. It should be noted that Healey has since put forward a different interpretation, however [42].

  10. Note also that the exact shape of the past region seemed not to enter, except insomuch as the region arguably has to be a certain shape to sufficiently specify the past (see Appendix A). As long as freedom of settings (7) refers to the same λ as Bell locality (6) the proof will go through.

  11. Morganti agrees with this proposal:

    At most, the evidence requires one to put into doubt what, following Jones, one may call ‘causal separability’, that is, the requirement that an event A can be the cause of another event B only if A has a part entirely in the past light cone of B that entirely causes B. Indeed, if the emergent property of the whole system is such that it is affected in its entirety by a measurement localized where one particle is and, as a consequence of this, determines a new categorical property of another particle at a different location, it is clear that causal separability fails. But this, as explained, is not in itself a violation of locality.

    ([22], p. 1033).The reference is to [43]. Morganti clearly states his belief that “locality,” which can be taken to share the meaning it is given here, can be preserved while making this move.

  12. The following quote from Morganti illustrates this:

    In other words, a measurement on an entangled system, commonly understood as an event E 1 localized where one of the particles is and determining another event E 2 localized where the other particle is in fact an event E 1 located everywhere the total system is (in particular, at the locations of both component particles) that determines events E 2 and E 3 localized at different places and yet in physical and spatiotemporal continuity with their cause, E 1. This means that one has a process that is entirely local at each stage.

    ([22], pp. 1031–1032). This seems consistent with the version made explicit here, and the quotes from Howard and Redhead given earlier in this section also tend in this direction.

  13. Laudisa also criticises Howard’s arguments on separability, and his main criticism turns on this point [23]. He argues that, if α and β are defined as representing these separate states, then the identifications (19) and (20) are not justified. For instance, in Bohm’s theory we might be tempted on this basis to make α just the position of the particle headed to the \(\mathcal {A}\) wing and similarly for β. But λ should also contain the quantum state in that case, as that is part of the ontology as well, and so (19) and (20) would not necessarily hold in that case. However, the association of the wave-function to a region has been left ambiguous here: there is nothing inconsistent with Bohm’s theory in including a copy of the quantum state at, say, every point in space (an observation made by Lucien Hardy, private communication), and so it could be in both α and β. The arguments against Howard’s views given here are different from Laudisa’s: for instance, Laudisa does not challenge Jarrett’s views on Bell’s theorem or Howard’s interpretation of Einstein. Related, though distinct, arguments are made in Appendix B. For now, we treat the equations simply as identifications that define the meaning of α and β, accepting Howard’s definitions, and assess the consequences of this.

  14. Healey recognises this when he writes, referring to the same quote from Einstein, that “[e]ach of A and B may be spatially localised and have its own state, even if the state of the nonlocalised AB does not supervene on the states of A and B” ([18], p. 352).

  15. He does say that local action is “applied consistently only in field theory,” which might seem to undermine the argument (originally from Healy [27]) that local action and separability are not linked, but a more plausible reading is that field theory was the only type of theory available at the time of writing in which local action is unambiguously enforced.

  16. This definition is at the level of the state/history space whereas, in Sect. 2.1, the slightly higher level of the algebra of events was used. In this article, the set of all events \(\varSigma(\mathcal {M})\) can be any σ-algebra on the history space, and so a condition like Harrigan and Spekkens’ would not be appropriate. But if Ω is countable and \(\varSigma (\mathcal {M})\) is fixed to be the Boolean algebra of subsets of Ω, the definitions coincide.

  17. Thanks to Michel Buck for pointing out this quote.

  18. Note that Bell does need his past variables to be associated to some past region, even if an infinite one. Therefore he is not arguing against the existence of localised events in the weakest sense here, although the spatial localisation of the wave-function might most naturally be an infinite region, which seems almost equivalent to saying it is not localised anywhere.

  19. In [10] Brown and Timpson make a careful distinction between causal principles based on the PCC and what they define as locality, and so their approach is anything but naïve to the sort of questions being raised here. Such reasoning could be applied to the other approaches listed here as well. Nevertheless they all explicitly attempt to reconcile locality with quantum mechanics, using definitions of locality similar to that employed here.

  20. This condition is called “strong” as it is possible to imagine weaker version of the condition that set \(\mathcal {D}\) to be the whole of \(J^{+}(\mathcal {X}) \cap J^{-}(\mathcal {X})\) or a slightly smaller region. However such versions would not save nouvelle locality, as they would still allow causal propagation via non-separable events which might span \(\mathcal {S}\).

  21. Something similar is probably true of other examples in which the whole past is not conditioned on, like Percival and Penrose’s causal condition in which the past region is a “wedge” such that the remainder of \(J^{+}(\mathcal {A}) \cup J^{-}(\mathcal {B})\) when the wedge is removed is a disjoint union of two regions, one containing \(\mathcal {A}\) and the other \(\mathcal {B}\) [52].

  22. This is also of relevance to Healey’s thesis that locality and local action can both be preserved in gauge field theory only if separability is sacrificed [27]. The events there are defined on closed spacelike curves. It would be interesting to formulate local action and locality as specifically as is done here, and to explicitly show that they are not violated for certain gauge theories in Healey’s picture of them.

  23. Other models can be imagined: for example, a spherical wave propagating out from one outcome that affects the other, or a string between a pair of entangled particles along which local actions could pass. If the question is what chance there is of formulating a natural and empirically adequate theory that manifests outcome dependence and separability, thoughts of this kind might be of interest (see [24] for a discussion); the question at hand, however, is whether separability implies separability of states over all theories, and so these considerations are not relevant. In this sense, Maudlin’s argument against Howard is not reliant on any ill-defined “intuitions about tachyons” [24].

  24. This argument is closely related to Norsen’s criticism of Jarrett’s interpretation of Bell’s theorem, which also depends on the definition of λ, although Norsen’s account goes into more depth. It can also be usefully compared to Laudisa’s criticism of Howard [23].

References

  1. Bell, J.: Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics, 2nd edn. Cambridge Univeristy Press, Cambridge (2004). Subsequent references to Bell’s papers will be made in-line with the year of publication and the page numbers from this book. The original publication details can be found therein

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Redhead, M.: Incompleteness, Nonlocality and Realism. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1987)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Cushing, J.T., McMullin, E. (eds.): Philosophical Consequences of Quantum Theory. Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame (1989). Subsequent references to papers in this collection will be made in-line with author’s name and the page numbers from this book

    Google Scholar 

  4. Maudlin, T.: In: Quantum Non-Locality and Relativity, Malden, Massachusetts (2002)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  5. Norsen, T.: Found. Phys. Lett. 19, 633 (2006). arXiv:quant-ph/0601205

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Norsen, T.: Arxiv preprint, 19 (2007)

  7. Norsen, T.: Found. Phys. 37, 311 (2007). arXiv:quant-ph/0607057

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  8. Norsen, T.: Found. Phys. 39, 273 (2009). arXiv:0808.2178

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. Butterfield, J.: Br. J. Philos. Sci. 43, 41 (1992). pss/687884

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  10. Timpson, C.G., Brown, H.R.: Entanglement and relativity. In: Lupacchini, R., Fano, V. (eds.) Understanding Physical Knowledge, University of Bologna, Bologna (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Henson, J.: Causality, Bell’s theorem, and ontic definiteness. In preparation

  12. Reichenbach, H.: The Direction of Time. University of California Press, Berkeley (1956), reissued 1991

    Google Scholar 

  13. Jarrett, J.: Noûs 18, 569 (1984)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  14. Wessels, L.: Noûs 19, 481 (1985)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  15. Maudlin, T.: Am. J. Phys. 78, 121 (2010)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  16. Howard, D.: Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 16, 171 (1985)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  17. Teller, P.: Br. J. Philos. Sci. 37, 71 (1986)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  18. Healey, R.: The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge Univeristy Press, Cambridge (1989)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  19. Healey, R.A.: J. Philos. 88, 393 (1991)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  20. Healey, R.: Philos. Top. 20, 181 (1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Healey, R.: Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 25, 337 (1994)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Morganti, M.: Philos. Sci. 76, 1027 (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Laudisa, F.: Br. J. Philos. Sci. 46, 309 (1995)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  24. Berkovitz, J.: Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 29, 183 (1998)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  25. Winsberg, E., Fine, A.: J. Philos. 3C, 80–97 (2003)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  26. Fogel, B.: Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 38, 920 (2007)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  27. Healey, R.: Gauging What’s Real. Oxford University Press, New York (2007)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  28. Butterfield, J.: Br. J. Philos. Sci. 57, 709 (2005)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  29. Spekkens, R.W.: Phys. Rev. A 75, 032110 (2007). arXiv:quant-ph/0401052

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  30. Harrigan, N., Spekkens, R.W.: Found. Phys. 40, 125 (2010). arXiv:0706.2661

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  31. Bartlett, S.D., Rudolph, T., Spekkens, R.W.: Phys. Rev. A 86, 012103 (2012). arXiv:1111.5057

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  32. Pusey, M.F., Barrett, J., Rudolph, T.: Nat. Phys. 8, 476 (2012). arXiv:1111.3328

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Spekkens, R.: Why I am not a psi-ontologist. Seminar given at Perimeter Institute, Waterloo ON, Canada (2012). http://pirsa.org/12050021/

  34. Spekkens, R.: FQXi essay contest. arXiv:1209.0023 (2012)

  35. Ghirardi, G., Grassi, R.: Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 25, 397 (1994)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  36. Henson, J.: Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 36, 519 (2005). quant-ph/0410051

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  37. Uffink, J.: Philos. Sci. 66, 525 (1999)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  38. Rédei, M., San Pedro, I.: Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 43, 84 (2012). arXiv:1204.4288

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Henson, J.: Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 44, 17 (2013). arXiv:1210.1463

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  Google Scholar 

  40. Seevinck, M., Uffink, J.: Not throwing out the baby with the bathwater: Bell’s condition of local causality mathematically ‘sharp and clean’. In: Dieks, D., Gonzalez, W.J., Hartmann, S., Uebel, T., Weber, M. (eds.) Explanation, Prediction, and Confirmation, vol. 2, pp. 425–450. Springer, Netherlands (2011). arXiv:1007.3724

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  41. Clauser, J., Horne, M., Shimony, A., Holt, R.: Phys. Rev. Lett. 26, 880 (1969)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  42. Healey, R.: Br. J. Philos. Sci. 63, 729 (2012). arXiv:1008.3896

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  43. Jones, M.R.: Locality and holism: the metaphysics of quantum theory. PhD thesis, Stanford University, Stanford, CA (1991)

  44. Jones, M., Clifton, R.K.: Against experimental metaphysics. In: French, P., Wehling, T., Wettstein, H. (eds.) Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 18, pp. 295–316. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  45. Einstein, A.: Dialectica 2, 320 (1948)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  46. Smerlak, M., Rovelli, C.: Found. Phys. 37, 427 (2007). quant-ph/0604064

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

  47. Fuchs, C.A.: arXiv:1003.5209 (2010)

  48. Hofer-Szabó, G., Rédei, M., Szabó, L.: Br. J. Philos. Sci. 50, 377 (1999)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  49. Hofer-Szabó, G., Rédei, M., Szabó, L.: Philos. Sci. 69, 623 (2002)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  50. Butterfield, J.: Br. J. Philos. Sci. 58, 805 (2007). arXiv:0708.2192

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  51. Reichenbach, H.: The Philosophic Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. University of California Press, Berkeley (1944), reprinted by Dover 1998

    Google Scholar 

  52. Penrose, R., Percival, I.: Proc. Phys. Soc. 79, 605 (1962)

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank Michel Buck for pointing out a useful quote from Bell, Fay Dowker and Rafael Sorkin for many conversations about causality and relativity, and especially to Harvey Brown for pointing to previous work on separability such as that of Healey. Thanks are also due to Travis Norsen and Rob Spekkens for edifying discussions of an earlier version on the manuscript. This work was made possible through the support of a grant from the John Templeton Foundation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joe Henson.

Appendices

Appendix A: A Complication: Local Action and Nouvelle Locality

In Sect. 2 it was argued that Bell locality can be formulated without first assuming separability. However, there is another definition of Bell’s “local causality” given in a later article ([1], 1990, pp. 232–248). It is reasonable to ask: it possible that, in order to use this definition of locality, we must assume separability? And would that be problematic for the main theses of this paper?

In this case, the past region is not taken to be whole causal past of any of the relevant regions. Instead we are asked to consider a “slice” of spacetime (a region between two spacelike hypersurfaces). Now, Eq. (5) must hold for the past region consisting of “at least those parts of [the slice] blocking the two backward lightcones,” that is, the intersection of the slice with the union of the causal pasts of \(\mathcal {A}\) and \(\mathcal {B}\). We will call this region \(\mathcal {S}\) and this version of the principle “nouvelle locality”. Bell writes that “what happens in the backwards lightcone of [the regions in question]” should be “sufficiently specified, for example by a full specification of local beables in [a slice of the past light cone]” ([1], 1990, p. 240, my italics). This suggests that Bell intended the condition to hold for any slice as long as we have reason to think that it “sufficiently specifies” the past. But what does, and how do we know it does?

Although nouvelle locality might look like a stronger condition than Bell locality, it is possible for correlations between events in \(\mathcal {A}\) and \(\mathcal {B}\) to be introduced rather than removed by conditioning on more past events, leading to the so-called “Simpson’s paradox” [36, 37]; this is essentially the reason why we must “sufficiently specify” the past. What if such a “Simpson’s paradox” arose due to past events outside of \(\mathcal {S}\)? These include events associated to regions to the past of \(\mathcal {S}\), as well as non-separable events lying partially to the past and partially to the future of it. It is reasonable to demand that our causal principle rules this out for the same reason as it should rule out correlations after conditioning on events in \(\mathcal {S}\).

From this is seems that conditioning on Bell’s “example,” the region \(\mathcal {S}\), only sufficiently specifies the past under certain conditions.

Strong Relativistic Local Action (SRLA)

for any two events X and Y belonging to regions \(\mathcal {X}\) and \(\mathcal {Y}\) such that \(\mathcal {X}\) lies entirely to the past of \(\mathcal {Y}\), the following condition holds:

$$ \mu(X|\lambda)\mu(Y|\lambda)= \mu(X \cap Y|\lambda) \quad\forall \lambda\in\varPhi\bigl( \mathcal {D}(\mathcal {A},\mathcal {B}) \bigr), $$
(22)

where \(\varPhi ( \mathcal {D}(\mathcal {X},\mathcal {Y}) )\) is the set of full specifications of the region \(\mathcal {D}(\mathcal {X},\mathcal {Y})\) which is the intersection of some slice with \(J^{+}(\mathcal {X}) \cap J^{-}(\mathcal {Y}) \backslash(\mathcal {X}\cup \mathcal {Y})\).Footnote 20

This rule seems strong enough to prevent influences from propagating from some past event to \(\mathcal {A}\) or \(\mathcal {B}\) without also showing up in \(\mathcal {S}\). I conjecture that, assuming SRLA for both cases, Bell locality and nouvelle locality will turn out to be equivalent.Footnote 21 A proof could conceivably run along roughly the same lines as those given in [36] for other variations on the shape of the past region. Without the SRLA assumption, conditioning only on events in a slice is problematic: they may not sufficiently specify the past, as Bell required.

It seems unlikely that Bell changed the shape of the past region with the intention of introducing an implicit local action assumption. Instead, the real intention of the change may have been to relieve worries expressed elsewhere. Bell refers to “the necessity of paying attention in such a study to the creation of the world” in a different context ([1], 1977, p. 102) and then, in a footnote, adds that “The invocation in [([1], 1975, pp. 52–62)] of a complete account of the overlap of the backward light cones is embarrassing in a related way, whether going back indefinitely or to a finite creation time… In more careful discussion the notion of completeness [full specification] should perhaps be replaced by that of sufficient completeness for a certain accuracy, with suitable epsilonics” ([1], 1977, p. 104). With nouvelle locality nothing arbitrarily far back into the past need be conditioned on, resolving this possible worry in a cleaner way. But there seems nothing wrong with Bell’s original pragmatic suggestion if we do not wish to make this move.

There is relevance to the discussion of separability. The condition rules out correlations due to a common cause amongst non-separable events that span \(\mathcal {S}\), or a correlation mediated to \(\mathcal {A}\) and \(\mathcal {B}\) by non-separable events that span \(\mathcal {S}\). This does not imply separability, but it does mean that it is not necessary to specify these non-separable events in order to screen off spacelike events. This threatens to trivialise their dynamics. But note that events associated to some subset of a spacelike hypersurface in \(\mathcal {S}\) do not face this problem because they cannot span \(\mathcal {S}\). So non-separable events of this kind cause no more problems when conditioning only on a slice. In one way the opposite is true: Bell does not rule out the extension of the past region to the whole of a slice in the above definition, in which case the specification could indeed include things like the quantum state which have no obvious “locality, or even localizability” in space at all.Footnote 22

In any case, the version of Bell locality used in Sect. 2.2 arguably is sensible despite Bell’s “embarrassment”. It is not obviously a problem to condition on events arbitrarily far into the past, because events do not have to be empirically accessible to be conditioned on in a model, as argued in [39]. The point of Bell’s theorem is that we cannot find a Bell local model that gives the same correlations as quantum mechanics no matter what we hypothesise about past events in our model. Also, locality and local action are different principles, and any condition that enforces locality need not also enforce local action.

In conclusion, whichever version of Bell’s condition we prefer, separability as defined in Sect. 2.1 need not be assumed in order to make the condition sensible, and so the main arguments in the paper are not threatened when this alternative formulation of Bell locality is considered.

Appendix B: Separability vs. Howard’s Separability of States

In this appendix, we will discuss Howard’s formalisation of separability of states, given in Sect. 3.3, and find the connection to the definition of separability in Sect. 2.1. The relevant definitions are (19) and (20) and the condition itself, Eq. (21).

It is useful to note at the outset that the definitions of μ α (a o |a s b s ) and μ β (b o |a s b s ) do not imply much about the meaning of the “states” α and β [23]. For example, consider a model of the EPRB experiment in which all the past events are associated to one point. In this case α and β clearly do not label initial states of two spatially disjoint systems corresponding to the two wings. However, it is possible to add an extra assumption that the relevant past region \(\mathcal {P}\) is the disjoint union of two regions, \(\mathcal {P}_{\mathcal {A}}\) and \(\mathcal {P}_{\mathcal {B}}\), which lie to the past of the \(\mathcal {A}\) and \(\mathcal {B}\) wings respectively (this would accord with local action and nouvelle locality as in the preceeding appendix).

Even making this assumption, it is easy to see that separability does not imply Eq. (21). Take for example a theory with correlations between the outcomes, but a past with no non-trivial events, separable or otherwise (or any model that gives these probabilities after conditioning on some separable past events). Maudlin gives a similar argument, adding to the picture some tachyons to make it more intuitive and “mechanical” (maintaining local action for instance) ([4], pp. 97–98).Footnote 23

To put a finer point on this, consider for example a “back-yard” EPRB-like experiment, which can be modelled as above, but in which the wings are not required to be spacelike. Let us imagine that one outcome A o (random, according to the theory we apply) triggers a ping-pong ball to be fired into the \(\mathcal {B}\) wing. By some simple mechanism, this affects the outcome there. To complete the argument, note that Howard’s original definitions of separability say nothing about whether the “regions of spacetime” concerned are spacelike or timelike to each other. Now, this back-yard experiment violates Howard’s formal condition (21) as applied to its “wings,” but obviously this simple scenario does not rely on violating Howard’s “fundamental ontological principle,” separability. It follows that the formal separability of states condition does not faithfully express a ban on non-separable events overlapping the two wings, the idea that the two wings are in fact two separate systems, the claim that basic properties are all associated to points, lack of mysterious“passion-at-a-distance” or anything of the sort. There is nothing motivating the condition—unless that is, we put the wings spacelike to each other, and invoke locality in order to prevent such scenarios. We already know that Howard’s separability of states condition follows from Bell’s locality condition, and it is best interpreted simply as a consequence of that well-founded condition.

Conversely Eq. (21) does not imply separability, or even the relevant consequence of separability: that the are no events associated to \(\mathcal {P}_{\mathcal {A}}\cup \mathcal {P}_{\mathcal {B}}\) that are not logical combinations of events associated to \(\mathcal {P}_{\mathcal {A}}\) and \(\mathcal {P}_{\mathcal {B}}\). The equation means nothing more or less than it explicitly says: that μ(a o b o |a s b s λ), where λ is the state of \(\mathcal {P}\), which may well have associated to it non-separable events, equals μ α (a o |a s b s )μ β (b o |a s b s ).

So much for the comparison itself. As in the main text, the more difficult question to answer is why the conclusions reached in this framework differ from those already in the literature. There is an implicit assumption in Howard’s treatment that resolves this problem. Howard and those who have developed his argument [25, 26] must keep the meaning of λ that Bell gave, in order to keep their arguments about separability of states in contact with the derivation of the Bell inequalities. Now, λ, for Bell, ranges over all full specifications of \(\mathcal {P}\) (see Sect. 2.2). However, Howard formally defines his “states” λ as p λ (x|m), which translates to μ(a o b o |a s b s λ) here ([3], Howard p. 226). The two definitions are only consistent if the following assumption holds: μ(a o b o |a s b s λ) completely determines the full specification λ, and similarly for α and β. This assumption is not part of the framework used in this paper, which is one reason for the discrepancy in conclusions. More importantly, the assumption is problematic. For example, if we add a third setting value, requiring the new condition for μ α (a o |a s b s ) does not imply the same condition for its restriction back to two settings. In other words, the argument goes through when our theory only allows our apparatus to have two marks on its dial, but not if we imagine a third unused mark!Footnote 24

Even given this assumption, there is another problem. Winsberg and Fine also argue that separability does not imply (21), but on the grounds that, to satisfy Howard’s principle, the joint “state” could determine the “states” of the wings [25] in any way, not necessarily through a product (see also Fogel’s detailed account [26]). With Howard’s implicit assumption, Winsberg and Fine’s weaker condition has some justification: if, as separability implies, the full specifications α and β determine λ, then the assumption implies that μ α (a o |a s b s ) and μ β (b o |a s b s ) will determine μ(a o b o |a s b s λ) (Fogel’s “functionwise” composition). However, when Winsberg and Fine conclude that both locality and separability can be preserved in the wake of Bell’s theorem, they are relying on the rest of Howard’s (and Jarrett’s) arguments, including this implicit, and flawed, assumption.

In conclusion, we saw in Sects. 3.3 and 3.4 that (a) even if we allow the definition of separability of states to go unquestioned, Howard’s argument that locality can be saved by dropping this condition is flawed, and (b) the attribution of the separability assumption to Einstein is questionable. We can now add that (c) the definition in Eq. (21) is not a good formalisation of the separability principle as Howard defines and discusses it.

This analysis is relevant to the so-called PBR theorem, which rules out the epistemic interpretation of quantum states under a number of conditions, including a so-called “preparation independence” condition [32] that bears some similarity to a separability condition. As the debate on this theorem and its conditions goes on, care must be taken to not to read too much into this condition. In this case, however, the line between epistemological and ontological concepts has been made clear by the original authors, giving hope that the discussion will remain clear-cut on this issue.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Henson, J. Non-separability Does Not Relieve the Problem of Bell’s Theorem. Found Phys 43, 1008–1038 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-013-9730-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-013-9730-8

Keywords

Navigation