Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-xtgtn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T17:47:56.143Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

PLACING PROBABILITIES OF CONDITIONALS IN CONTEXT

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 May 2014

RONNIE HERMENS*
Affiliation:
University of Groningen
*
*FACULTY OF PHILOSOPHY, UNIVERSITY OF GRONINGEN, OUDE BOTERINGESTRAAT 52, 9712 GL GRONINGEN, THE NETHERLANDS E-mail: r.hermens@rug.nl

Abstract

In this paper I defend the tenability of the Thesis that the probability of a conditional equals the conditional probability of the consequent given the antecedent. This is done by adopting the view that the interpretation of a conditional may differ from context to context. Several triviality results are (re-)evaluated in this view as providing natural constraints on probabilities for conditionals and admissible changes in the interpretation. The context-sensitive approach is also used to re-interpret some of the intuitive rules for conditionals and probabilities such as Bayes’ rule,Import-Export, and Modus Ponens. I will show that, contrary to consensus, the Thesis is in fact compatible with these re-interpreted rules.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 2014 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Adams, E. W. (1975). The Logic of Conditionals. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Bennett, J. (2003). A Philosophical Guide to Conditionals. Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackburn, S. (1986). How can we tell whether a commitment has a truth condition? In Travis, C., editor. Meaning and Interpretation. Oxford, England: Basil Blackwell,pp. 201232.Google Scholar
Bradley, R. (2011). Conditionals and supposition-based reasoning. Topoi, 30, 3945.Google Scholar
Bradley, R. (2012). Multidimensional possible-world semantics for conditionals. The Philosophical Review, 121, 539571.Google Scholar
Briggs, R. (2014). Two interpretations of the Ramsey test. In Beebee, H., Hitchcock, C., & Price, H., editors. Making a Difference. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press (Forthcoming).Google Scholar
Döring, F. (1994). On the probabilities of conditionals. The Philosophical Review, 103, 689700.Google Scholar
Douven, I. (2011). Indicative conditionals. In Horsten, L., & Pettigrew, R., editors. The Continuum Companion to Philosophical Logic, London: Continuum International Publishing Group, pp. 383405.Google Scholar
Douven, I., & Dietz, R. (2011). A puzzle about Stalnaker’s hypothesis. Topoi, 30, 3137.Google Scholar
Douven, I., & Verbrugge, S. (2010). The adams family. Cognition, 117, 302318.Google Scholar
Douven, I., & Verbrugge, S. (2013). The probabilities of conditionals revisited. Cognitive Science, 37, 711730.Google Scholar
Edgington, D. (1995). On conditionals. Mind, 104(414), 235329.Google Scholar
Etlin, D. (2009). The problem of noncounterfactual conditionals. Philosophy of Science, 76, 676688.Google Scholar
Evans, J. S. B. T., Handley, S. J., & David, O. E. (2003). Conditionals and conditional probability. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 29, 321335.Google ScholarPubMed
Evans, J. S. B. T., Handley, S. J., Neilens, H., & Over, D. E. (2007). Thinking about conditionals: A study of individual differences. Memory and Cognition, 35, 17591771.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. (1981). Two recent theories of conditionals. In Harper, W. L., Stalnaker, R., & Pearce, G., editors. Ifs. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, pp. 211247.Google Scholar
Gillies, A. S. (2009). On truth-conditions for if (but not quite only if). The Philosophical Review, 118, 325349.Google Scholar
Hadjichristidis, C., Stevenson, R. J., Over, D. E., Sloman, S. A., Evans, J. S. B. T., & Feeney, A. (2001). On the evaluation of ‘if p then q’ conditionals. In Moore, J. D., & Stenning, K., editors. Proceedings of the Twenty-Third Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. London: Psychology Press, pp. 381386.Google Scholar
Hájek, A. (1989). Probabilities of conditionals – revisited. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 18, 423428.Google Scholar
Hájek, A. (1994). Triviality on the cheap? In Eels, E., & Skyrms, B., editors. Probability and Conditionals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 113140.Google Scholar
Hájek, A. (2011). Triviality pursuit. Topoi, 30, 315.Google Scholar
Hájek, A. (2012). The fall of “Adams’ thesis”? Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 21, 145161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hájek, A., & Hall, N. (1994). The hypothesis of the conditional construal of conditional probability. In Eels, E., & Skyrms, B., editors. Probability and Conditionals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 75111.Google Scholar
Hall, N. (1994). Back in the CCCP. In Eels, E., & Skyrms, B., editors. Probability and Conditionals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 141160.Google Scholar
Harper, W. L. (1976). Ramsey test conditionals and iterated belief change. In Harper, W. L., & Hooker, C. A., editors. Foundations of Probability Theory, Statistical Inference, and Statistical Theories of Science I. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, pp. 117135.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R. (1991). Matter-of-fact conditionals I. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 65, 161183.Google Scholar
Karnaugh, M. (1953). The map method for synthesis of combinational logic circuits. Transactions of the American Institute of Electrical Engineers, 72(9), 593599.Google Scholar
Kaufmann, S. (2009). Conditionals right and left: Probabilities for the whole family. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 38, 153.Google Scholar
Leitgeb, H. (2012). A probabilistic semantics for counterfactuals. Part A. Review of Symbolic Logic, 5(1), 2684.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1976). Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities. The Philosophical Review, LXXXV(3), 297315.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1986). Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities II. The Philosophical Review, XCV(4), 581589.Google Scholar
Lindström, S. (1996). The Ramsey test and the indexicality of conditionals: A proposed resolution of gärdenfors’ paradox. In Fuhrmann, A., & Rott, H., editors. Logic, Action, and Information: Essays on Logic in Philosophy and Artificial Intelligence. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co, pp. 208228.Google Scholar
Lindström, S., & Rabinowicz, W. (1996). The ramsey test revisited. In Crocco, G., Del Cerro, L. F. n., & Herzig, A., editors. Conditionals. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, pp. 147191.Google Scholar
McGee, V. (1985). A counterexample to modus ponens. The Journal of Philosophy, 82(9), 462471.Google Scholar
McGee, V. (1989). Conditional probabilities and compounds of conditionals. The Philosophical Review, 98(4), 485541.Google Scholar
Milne, P. (2003). The simplest Lewis-style triviality proof yet? Analysis, 63(4), 300303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oberauer, K., Weidenfeld, A., & Fischer, K. (2007). What makes us believe a conditional? The roles of covariation and causality. Thinking & Reasoning, 13, 340369.Google Scholar
Over, D. E. (1987). Assumptions and the supposed counterexamples to modus ponens. Analysis, 47, 142146.Google Scholar
Over, D. E., & Evans, J. S. B. T. (2003). The probability of conditionals: The psychological evidence. Mind and Language, 18, 340358.Google Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. (1931). General propositions and causality. In Braithwaite, R. B., editor. Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd, pp. 237255.Google Scholar
Rehder, W. (1982). Conditions for probabilities of conditionals to be conditional probabilities. Synthese, 53, 439443.Google Scholar
Romeijn, J-W. (2012). Conditioning and interpretation shifts. Studia Logica, 100(3),583606.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1970). Probability and conditionals. Philosophy of Science, 37, 6480.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1975). Indicative conditionals. Philosophia, 5, 269286.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1976). Letter to van Fraassen. In Harper, W. L., & Hooker, C. A., editors. Foundations of Probability Theory, Statistical Inference, and Statistical Theories of Science I. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, pp. 302306.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R., & Jeffrey, R. (1994). Conditionals as random variables. In Eels, E., & Skyrms, B., editors. Probability and Conditionals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 3146.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1976). Probabilities of conditionals. In Harper, W. L., & Hooker, C. A., editors. Foundations of Probability Theory, Statistical Inference, and Statistical Theories of Science I. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, pp. 261300.Google Scholar
Weidenfeld, A., Oberauer, K., & Hörnig, R. (2005). Causal and causal conditionals: An integrated model of interpretation and reasoning. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology Section A, 58, 14791513.Google Scholar
Williams, J. R. G. (2012). Counterfactual triviality: A Lewis-impossibility argument for counterfactuals. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85, 648670.Google Scholar