Skip to main content
Log in

The dialectics of infinitism and coherentism: inferential justification versus holism and coherence

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper formally explores the common ground between mild versions of epistemological coherentism and infinitism; it proposes—and argues for—a hybrid, coherentist–infinitist account of epistemic justification. First, the epistemological regress argument and its relation to the classical taxonomy regarding epistemic justification—of foundationalism, infinitism and coherentism—is reviewed. We then recall recent results proving that an influential argument against infinite regresses of justification, which alleges their incoherence on account of probabilistic inconsistency, cannot be maintained. Furthermore, we prove that the Principle of Inferential Justification has rather unwelcome consequences—formally resembling the Sorites paradox—as soon as it is iterated and combined with a natural Bayesian perspective on probabilistic inferences. We conclude that strong versions of foundationalism and infinitism should be abandoned. Positively, we provide a rough sketch for a graded formal coherence notion, according to which infinite regresses of epistemic justification will often have more than a minimal degree of coherence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I am very grateful to an anonymous referee for pointing out several weaknesses in an earlier version of this section and the following one; any remaining errors are mine.

  2. Mnemonics: the letter \({\fancyscript{I}}\) abbreviates ‘individual’; \(S\) abbreviates ‘sentence’.

  3. The second half of this requirement is, strictly speaking, redundant—because we have already demanded \(S_1,S_2,\ldots \) to be propositions other than \(S_0\)—and has only been inserted for clarification.

  4. In Peijnenburg’s Peijnenburg (2007) or Peijnenburg and Atkinson’s Peijnenburg and Atkinson (2008) terminology, confirmation is referred to as probabilistic support. Since this is not the standard Bayesian terminology and we use the verb ‘to support’ also in a different formal sense (viz. when referring to the set of probability measures supporting a belief system), we have chosen not to follow Peijnenburg’s example on this minor point.

  5. He was corrected by Reichenbach in a private letter and admitted his error, as explained by Peijnenburg and Atkinson (2008, p. 338).

  6. As a few elementary rearrangements show:

    $$\begin{aligned} P(E|F)>P(E|\complement F)&\Leftrightarrow \frac{P(E\cap F)}{P(F)}>\frac{P(E\setminus F)}{1-P(F)} \\&\Leftrightarrow P(E\cap F)-P(E\cap F)P(F)>P(E\setminus F)P(F)\\&\Leftrightarrow P(E\cap F)>P(E)P(F) \Leftrightarrow P(E|F)>P(E). \end{aligned}$$
  7. On this point, I am indebted to an anonymous referee, who suggested the following example. Suppose there is a 1,000 ticket lottery, \(F\) is the event that ticket #1,000 does not win, and \(E\) is the event that ticket #1 wins. Suppose you learn from a reliable source that \(F\) is true, so you are justified in believing it, and condition (1) in (BPIJ) is met. So is (2): \(P\left( E | F\right) = 1/999 > 1/1\),\(000\). But surely you are not justified in believing \(E\) on the basis of \(F\). In terms of Bayesian confirmation theory, the degree of confirmation for \(E\) offered by \(F\) (according to the relevance measure of confirmation) is minute, viz. just \(1/999 -1/1\),\(000\), which is of order \(10^{-6}\).

  8. A popular version of what is known as the Lockean thesis demands that in order for a proposition \(S_0\) to be considered a full belief of an agent, that agent’s degree of belief in \(S_0\) must exceed a certain threshold. Locke’s Essay contains several passages that suffer such an interpretation (Locke (1979) Book IV, Chapters XIV–XVII).

  9. The choice of such a sequence is possible in light of the consistency theorems for infinite regresses, cf. Sect. 5.

  10. This may be all the more surprising since coherentism was, after all, the position of eminent analytic epistemologists such as Goodman (1951), Hempel (1935a,b), Neurath (1931, 1932), Quine and Ullian (1970), Reichenbach (1938) and Sellars (1963) to name but a few; among influential contemporary epistemologists, coherentism has had adherents such as van Fraassen (1984), and Jeffrey (1992) at the very least shared their opposition to foundationalism.

  11. Reichenbach already proposed a solution to the isolation objection along these lines through the inclusion of “observation sentences” (Reichenbach 1952, p. 159; 1938, p. 83) or “protocol sentences” (Lewis 1952, p. 171.)

  12. Herein, \(\varnothing \) denotes the minimal element of the algebra \({\fancyscript{A}}\) of propositions, viz. the empty set when identifying each proposition in \({\fancyscript{A}}\) with its extension, i.e. the set of worlds in which it holds.

  13. It is interesting in this connection that de Finetti considered probabilistic consistency to be such an important component of a coherence notion that he simply defined coherence as probabilistic consistency (de Finetti 1937, 1970, 1974).

  14. Herein, \(\Omega \) denotes the maximal element of the algebra \({\fancyscript{A}}\) of propositions, viz. the set of all possible worlds when identifying each proposition in \({\fancyscript{A}}\) with its extension (the set of worlds in which it holds).

References

  • Adams, E. W. (1998). A primer of probability logic. CSLI lecture notes. Stanford: CSLI Publications. With a foreword by Brian Skyrms.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle, Jenkinson A. J., & Mure, G. R. G. (2006). Prior analytics and posterior analytics. Bloomington: Authorhouse.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. (2011). Epistemology: A contemporary introduction to the theory of knowledge (3rd ed.). Oxford: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, J. (1969). Aristotle’s theory of demonstration. Phronesis, 14(2), 123–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergmann, M. (2004). What’s not wrong with foundationalism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 68, 161–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (2010). The myth of knowledge. Philosophical Perspectives, 24(1), 57–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bovens, L., & Hartmann, S. (2003). Bayesian epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brendel, E. (1999). Coherence theory of knowledge: A gradational account. Erkenntnis, 50(2–3), 293–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1950). Logical foundations of probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1962). The aim of inductive logic. In E. Nagel, P. Suppes, & A. Tarski (Eds.), Logic, methodology and philosophy of science (pp. 303–318). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. M. (1989). Theory of knowledge (3rd ed.). Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Finetti, B. (1937). La prévision: Ses lois logiques, ses sources subjectives. Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincaré, 7(1), 1–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Finetti, B. (1970). Teoria delle probabilità: Sintesi introduttiva con appendice critica. Volumi primo e secondo. Giulio Einaudi Editore: Nuova Biblioteca Scientifica Einaudi.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Finetti, B. (1974). Theory of probability: a critical introductory treatment (Antonio Machì & Adrian Smith, Trans.). New York: Wiley. With a foreword by D. V. Lindley.

  • Easwaran, K., & Fitelson, B. (2012). An “evidentialist” worry about Joyce’s argument for probabilism. Dialectica, 66(3), 425–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fajardo, S., & Keisler, H. J. (2002). Model theory of stochastic processes. Lecture Notes in Logic 14. Natick: Peters.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitelson, B., & McCarthy, D. (2012). Steps toward a new foundation for subjective probability. Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy, (work in progress).

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1984). Belief and the will. Journal of Philosophy, 81(5), 235–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (1998). Replies to my three critics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58, 927–937.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (2010). Foundationalist theories of epistemic justification. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford: Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1951). The structure of appearance. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A., & Hartmann, S. (2010). Bayesian epistemology. In J. Dancy, E. Sosa, & M. Steup (Eds.), A companion to epistemology (pp. 93–106). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hausdorff, F. (1918). Dimension und äußeres Maß. Mathematische Annalen, 79(1–2), 157–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1935). On the logical positivists’ theory of truth. Analysis, 2(4), 49–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1935). Some remarks on ‘facts’ and propositions. Analysis, 2(6), 93–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herzberg, F. S. (2010). The consistency of probabilistic regresses. A reply to Jeanne Peijnenburg and David Atkinson. Studia Logica, 94(3), 331–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herzberg, F. S. (2012). The consistency of probabilistic regresses: Some implications for epistemological infinitism. Erkenntnis, (forthcoming). doi:10.1007/s10670-011-9358-z.

  • Hoover, D. N., & Keisler, H. J. (1984). Adapted probability distributions. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 286, 159–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Irwin, T. H. (1988). Aristotle’s first principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. C. (1992). Probability and the art of judgment. Cambridge studies in probability, induction, and decision theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J. M. (2009). Accuracy and coherence: Prospects for an alethic epistemology of partial belief. In F. Huber & C. Schmidt-Petri (Eds.), Degrees of belief. Synthese library, 342 (pp. 263–297). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Klein, P. (1998). Foundationalism and the infinite regress of reasons. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58, 919–925.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1999). Human knowledge and the infinite regress of reasons. Philosophical Perspectives, 13, 297–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2005). Infinitism is the solution to the regress problem. In M. Steup & S. Ernest (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 131–140). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2007). How to be an infinitist about doxastic justification. Philosophical Studies, 134, 25–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2011). Skepticism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Summer 2011 edition.

  • Klein, P., & Warfield, T. A. (1994). What price coherence? Analysis, 54(3), 129–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P., & Warfield, T. A. (1996). No help for the coherentist. Analysis, 56(2), 118–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. (2011). Coherentist theories of epistemic justification. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Summer 2011 edition.

  • Lehrer, K. (2000). Theory of knowledge. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leitgeb, H., & Pettigrew, R. (2010). An objective justification of Bayesianism I. Measuring inaccuracy. Philosophy of Science, 77(2), 201–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leitgeb, H., & Pettigrew, R. (2010). An objective justification of Bayesianism II. The consequences of minimizing inaccuracy. Philosophy of Science, 77(2), 236–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C. I. (1952). The given element in empirical knowledge. Philosophical Review, 61, 168–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1979). In P. H. Nidditch (Ed.), An essay concerning human understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maher, P. (1996). Subjective and objective confirmation. Philosophy of Science, 63(2), 149–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, P. (2006). Coherentism in epistemology. Internet encyclopedia of philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/coherent/.

  • Neurath, O. (1931). Soziologie im physikalismus. Erkenntnis, 2, 393–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, O. (1932). Protokollsätze. Erkenntnis, 3, 204–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peijnenburg, J. (2007). Infinitism regained. Mind, 116(463), 597–602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peijnenburg, J., & Atkinson, D. (2008). Probabilistic justification and the regress problem. Studia Logica, 89(3), 333–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peijnenburg, J., & Atkinson, D. (2011). Grounds and limits: Reichenbach and foundationalist epistemology. Synthese, 181(1), 113–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peijnenburg, J., & Atkinson, D. (2013). The emergence of justification. Philosophical Quarterly, (forthcoming).

  • Quine, W. V. O., & Ullian, J. (1970). The web of belief. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1938). Experience and prediction. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1952). Are phenomenal reports absolutely certain? Philosophical Review, 61(2), 147–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1974). Foundationalism, coherentism, and the idea of cognitive systematization. Journal of Philosophy, 71(19), 695–708.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, A. (1966). Non-standard analysis. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

  • Russell, B. (1948). Human knowledge. London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1963). Science, perception, and reality. New York: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (1998). How to understand the foundations of empirical belief in a coherentist way. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 98(1), 23–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stump, E. (1991). Aquinas on the foundations of knowledge. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 17, 125–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, R. (2012). Outright belief. Dialectica, 66(3), 309–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This work was financially supported by the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation through a Visiting Fellowship of the Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy at Ludwig Maximilian University of Munich. I am deeply grateful to Professors Hannes Leitgeb and Stephan Hartmann for very helpful discussions, as well as to Professor Jeanne Peijnenburg and an anonymous referee for many insightful comments that helped to improve the paper substantially.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Frederik Herzberg.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Herzberg, F. The dialectics of infinitism and coherentism: inferential justification versus holism and coherence. Synthese 191, 701–723 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0273-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0273-5

Keywords

Navigation