Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Abstract

Presupposition is the semantic-pragmatic phenomenon whereby a statement contains an implicit precondition that must be taken for granted (presupposed) for that statement to be felicitous. This article discusses the role of presupposition in legislative texts, using examples from Swiss constitutional and administrative law. It illustrates (a) how presuppositions are triggered in these texts and (b) what functions they come to serve, placing special emphasis on their constitutive power. It also demonstrates (c) how legislative drafters can distinguish between “good” presuppositions and “bad” presuppositions by weighing their main advantage, conciseness, against their main flaw, reduced transparency. The present study argues that, if employed carefully, presuppositions can be a useful stylistic means to keep legislative texts free from unnecessary clutter that merely elaborates on the obvious; however, it also suggests that, if applied wrongly, presuppositions can camouflage the duties and obligations placed on the subjects of a law and thus impede its accessibility and its efficient and effective implementation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Marmor [15, 16, 17] refers to the respective set of phenomena as “semantically implied content” or “semantically encoded implication/semantically encoded presupposition”.

  2. Swiss federal law is drafted in German and in French and then translated into Italian. Once published, all three language versions are considered equally authentic [14]. In this paper, I will specifically look at examples from German-language texts. For each example, I will provide the authentic German wording as well as a translation into English.

  3. Proponents of the latter mostly argue that presuppositions represent a form of implicature.

  4. Beaver and Guerts point out that “[i]t makes sense to try several such embeddings when testing for presupposition, because it is not always clear how to apply a given embedding diagnostic. Thus, for example, […] although it is widely agreed that too is a presupposition-inducing expression, the negation test is awkward to apply in this case” [3, p. 2435].

  5. For a general discussion of the use of shall in English-language legislative texts, cf. [31].

  6. The definite description the Queen here refers to Queen Victoria (reign 1837–1901).

  7. Moreover, the role of the newly-created Federal Assembly corresponded to the role that the Diet had in the Old Swiss Confederacy. The use of a presupposition may thus also have been aimed at expressing an element of constitutional continuity.

  8. http://www.parlament.ch > Dokumentation > Berichte > Vernehmlassungen > 11.446—Pa.Iv. Für ein Auslandschweizergesetz (last visited on 22/10/2013).

  9. The role of the drafting committee of the Swiss federal administration has been discussed in [19].

  10. Compare the wording in the authentic French version: “Les barèmes, les taux et les montants exonérés de l’impôt, notamment, ne sont pas soumis à l’harmonisation fiscale.

  11. In the present case, the negation test cannot be used to assess whether the implied content is a presupposition: it is unclear how a sentence that contains the adverbial in particular is to be negated (cf. Beaver and Guerts [3, p. 2435] on the related problem of negating sentences containing the adverb too). However, the implied content can be shown to be a presupposition because it is preserved if the statement is transformed into a question: Are tax scales, tax rates, and tax allowances in particular excepted from harmonisation?

  12. Note that there is a second presupposition in sentence (18), triggered by the modal adverbial according to the following criteria (cf. Sect. 3.2): the procedural provision that the eligibility of an institution needs to be assessed by the CTI is in fact also merely presupposed rather than asserted. The sentence thus contains the following three provisions: (a) that to be eligible for grants, research institutions must be non-commercial, (b) that the eligibility of research institutions must be assessed by the CTI, and (c) that said assessment must be made according to the criteria listed thereafter. Only (c) is asserted, (a) and (b) are merely presupposed.

References

  1. Atlas, J., and Levinson, S. 1981. It-clefts, informativeness and logical form: Radical pragmatics. In Radical pragmatics, ed. P. Cole, 1–61. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Beaver, D. 2001. Presupposition and assertion in dynamic semantics. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Beaver, D., and Guerts, B. 2012. Presupposition. In Semantics, Handbücher zur Sprach- und Kommunikationswissenschaft / Handbooks of linguistics and communication science (HSK), vol. 33.3, eds. C. Maienborn, K. von Heusinger, P. Portner, 2432–2460. Amsterdam: De Gruyter.

  4. Federal Office of Justice (ed.). 2007. Gesetzgebungsleitfaden: Leitfaden für die Ausarbeitung von Erlassen des Bundes, 3rd edn. Bern.

  5. Frege, G. 1892/1984. Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und Philosophische Kritik 100:25–50.

  6. Gazdar, G. 1979. Pragmatics. Implicature, presupposition and logical form. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Grice, H.P. 1975. Logic and conversation. In Speech acts, syntax and semantics. ed. P. Cole, J.L. Morgan, vol. 3, 41–58. New York: Academic Press.

  8. Heim, I. 1983. On the projection problem for presuppositions. In Proceedings of the second annual west coast conference on formal linguistics (WCCFL). eds. M. Barlow, D. Flickinger, M. Wescoat, 114–126. CA: Stanford.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Höfler, S. 2011. “Ein Satz – eine Aussage”: Multipropositionale Rechtssätze an der Sprache erkennen. LeGes 22(2): 259–279.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Karttunen, L. 1974. Presuppositions and linguistic context. Theoretical Linguistics 1:181–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Karttunen, L., and Peters, S. 1979. Conventional implicatures. In Presupposition, syntax and semantics, vol. 11, eds. C.K. Oh, D.A. Dinneen, 1–56. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Lewis, D. 1979. Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philosophical Logic 8:339–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Linke, A., and Nussbaumer, M. 2000. Konzepte des Impliziten: Präsuppositionen und Implikaturen. In Text- und Gesprächslinguistik / Linguistics of Text and Conversation, Handbücher zur Sprach- und Kommunikationswissenschaft / Handbooks of linguistics and communication science (HSK), vol. 16.1, 435–448. Amsterdam: De Gruyter.

  14. Lötscher, A. 2009. Multilingual law drafting in Switzerland. In Formal linguistics and law, trends in linguistics, vol. 12, ed. G. Grewendorf, M. Rathert. 371–400. Berlin: De Gruyter.

  15. Marmor, A. 2007. What does the law say? Semantics and pragmatics in statutory language. Analisi e diritto 127.

  16. Marmor, A. 2008. The pragmatics of legal language. Ratio Juris 21(4): 423–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Marmor, A. 2011. Can the law imply more than it says? On some pragmatic aspects of strategic speech. In Philosophical foundations of language in the law, ed. A. Marmor, S. Soames. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  18. Müller, G. 2013. Die Totalrevision der Bundesverfassung zwischen Nachführung und materiellen Reformen. LeGes 24(2):351–358.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Nussbaumer, M. 2008. Der Verständlichkeit eine Anwältin! Die Redaktionskommission der schweizerischen Bundesverwaltung und ihre Arbeit an der Gesetzessprache. In Verständlichkeit als Bürgerrecht? Die Rechts- und Verwaltungssprache in der öffentlichen Diskussion, ed. K.M. Eichhoff-Cyrus, G. Antos, 301–323. Mannheim: Duden.

  20. Rosenbaum, K.L. 2007. Legislative drafting guide: A practitioner’s view. FAO Legal Papers Online 64.

  21. Russell, B. 1905. On denoting. Mind 14:479–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. van der Sandt, R.A. 1992. Presupposition projection as anaphora resolution. Journal of Semantics 9:333–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Schlenker, P. 2008. Be articulate. A pragmatic theory of presupposition. Theoretical Linguistics 34:157–212.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Searle, J.R. 1995. The construction of social reality. London: Penguin.

  25. Seuren, P. 1991. Präsuppositionen. In Semantik, Handbücher zur Sprach- und Kommunikationswissenschaft / Handbooks of linguistics and communication science (HSK), vol. 6, eds. A. von Stechow., D. Wunderlich, 286–318. Amsterdam: De Gruyter.

  26. Soames, S. 1989. Presupposition. In Handbook of philosophical logic, ed. D. Gabbay, F. Guenthner, vol. 4, 553–616. Dordrecht: Reidel.

  27. Stalnaker, R. 1973. Presupposition. The Journal of Philosophical Logic 2:447–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Strawson, P.F. 1950. On referring. Mind 59:320–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Strawson, P.F. 1952. Introduction to logical theory. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Tschannen, P. 2011. Staatsrecht der Schweizerischen Eidgenossenschaft, 3rd edn. Bern: Stämpfli.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Williams, C. 2006. Fuzziness in legal English: What shall we do with shall? In Legal language and the search for clarity: Practice and tools, studies in language and communication, ed. A. Wagner, S. Cacciaguidi-Fahy, vol. 37, 237–263. Bern: Lang.

  32. Wilson, D. 1975. Presupposition and non-truth-conditional semantics. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The work presented in this article was funded under Swiss National Science Foundation Grant No. 134701. It has benefited from regular exchanges with the Central Language Services of the Swiss Federal Chancellery.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stefan Höfler.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Höfler, S. Between Conciseness and Transparency: Presuppositions in Legislative Texts. Int J Semiot Law 27, 627–644 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-013-9337-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-013-9337-6

Keywords

Navigation