Skip to main content
Log in

A new direction for science and values

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The controversy over the old ideal of “value-free science” has cooled significantly over the past decade. Many philosophers of science now agree that even ethical and political values may play a substantial role in all aspects of scientific inquiry. Consequently, in the last few years, work in science and values has become more specific: Which values may influence science, and in which ways? Or, how do we distinguish illegitimate from illegitimate kinds of influence? In this paper, I argue that this problem requires philosophers of science to take a new direction. I present two case studies in the influence of values on scientific inquiry: feminist values in archaeology and commercial values in pharmaceutical research. I offer a preliminary assessment of these cases, that the influence of values was legitimate in the feminist case, but not in the pharmaceutical case. I then turn to three major approaches to distinguish legitimate from illegitimate influences of values, including the distinction between epistemic and non-epistemic values and Heather Douglas’ distinction between direct and indirect roles for values. I argue that none of these three approaches gives an adequate analysis of the two cases. In the concluding section, I briefly sketch my own approach, which draws more heavily on ethics than the others, and is more promising as a solution to the current problem. This is the new direction in which I think science and values should move.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I am not interested in the scientific realism vs. antirealism debate here, or the nature of truth as such. Rather, my interest is in our attitudes towards truth, the ways in which we pursue it, and how these pursuits relate to other activities. That is, I’m interested in these relational properties of truth rather than its intrinsic properties. Throughout this paper, I generally use “truth” as a generic term for the epistemic aim or aims of scientific inquiry, especially when and insofar as these are “purely epistemic,” that is, independent of or contrasting with the aims of “applied science” and engineering.

    Truth in the sense usually connected to scientific realism is one such aim, but other such aims include Bas van Fraassen’s empirical adequacy (1980) and Michael Friedman’s communicative rationality (2001). Daniel Steel seems to use “truth” in something like the narrower, scientific realist sense, and so when I discuss his views in Sect. 4 I follow his lead; however, little or nothing in the argument of that section turns on the nature of truth or scientific realism vs. antirealism. Truth in the Deweyan sense of “effectively resolves the current problematic situation” is not covered by “truth” as I use it there, since this sense of “truth” ties it closely to the pragmatic, not “purely epistemic” aims of “applied science” and engineering (Brown 2012).

    Throughout this paper, I speak of truth “as a value,” and discuss how this value relates to ethical and political values. Again, my interest is in our attitude towards truth—how we value it—and how this relates to other things that we value. Speaking of truth in this way does not imply that it is “merely” a value, that truth as such is entirely subjective, and so on. Indeed, presumably we value truth (in any of the senses given in the last paragraph) because it is not entirely subjective. Talking about truth as a value is entirely consistent with taking truth or some necessary condition for truth to be a necessary condition for accepting a theory. For instance, it is entirely consistent with taking internal consistency to be necessary for accepting a theory on the grounds that internal consistency is necessary for truth. Indeed, in this case we are attaching a great deal of value to truth; this is what I have in mind by the lexical priority of truth, discussed below. This way of using “value” differs somewhat from Douglas (2009, pp. 94–5), though not so much from Douglas (2013). See also note 13. I thank several readers, including an anonymous reviewer at Synthese, for encouraging me to clarify my use of “truth” and “truth as a value.”

  2. I use such terms as “hypotheses,” “theories,” “models,” and “accounts” roughly interchangeably throughout this paper, and take no position in the debates over the syntactical and semantic views or the status and role of models.

  3. I thank an anonymous reviewer at Synthese for pushing me to present the terminology in this section more precisely.

  4. Since isolationism and transactionism are defined in terms of specifically “ethical and political” values, for the sake of presentation I often simply abbreviate this as “values.” In Sect. 4, where I focus on the distinction between epistemic and non-epistemic values, I am more careful about this.

  5. To be clear, I don’t think that these three sets of tools are mutually exclusive. While the second and third—the distinction between epistemic and non-epistemic values and the distinction between direct and indirect roles for values, respectively—seem to be taken as rivals by their proponents, both involve the first, which is an assumption that Matthew Brown calls the lexical priority of evidence and which I generalize as the lexical priority of truth.

  6. Hicks (2012, Sect. 5.2).

  7. I do not have the space here to present two other analyses. One develops Robert Merton’s ethos of science; for examples see van den Belt (2010) and Radder (2010). Another points to the role of deceit in the pharmaceutical case.

  8. On my use of “truth as a value,” see note 1.

  9. Recall from note 1 that I am not assuming any specific conception of truth, or even whether “truth” is a more appropriate term than, say, “empirical adequacy”; and by “truth as a value” I mean truth regarded as good and worth having (by us), whatever truth is as such.

  10. I thank Charles Pence for pressing this point.

  11. The Knobe Effect suggests that the value we assign to the consequences of the Paxil trial will influence our assessment of the role of commercial values in the researchers’ intentions and reasoning, and so our assessment of the case according to Douglas’ account. Specifically, the effect predicts that we, insofar as we take these consequences to be bad, we will probably say that the researchers intended to bring them about (Knobe 2003). And it is reasonable to interpret this as an illegitimate direct role for values in the epistemic phase. I thank an anonymous reviewer for this point.

  12. The terminology of constitutive and contextual values is due to Longino (1990, 4ff), and these concepts have not enjoyed much further development in recent years. An anonymous reviewer suggests that Kitcher’s account of broad, cognitive, and probative values is a development of Longino’s concepts (Kitcher 2011, pp. 37–39; see also Brown 2013a).

  13. Up to this point in the paper, I have generally used “values” because it is the term used in the literature that I am discussing, viz., the “science and values” literature. However, my approach is better put in the language of various goods, which are the aims or ends or goals of various activities or social practices. Some of these goods are the constitutive aims of these activities; for example, truth and useful technology are two goods that are among the constitutive aims of the activity of scientific inquiry. For the sake of continuity with the rest of this paper, in the text I will stick with “values,” though occasionally this makes for some awkward phrasing. Compare the language of this note with Longino (1990, pp. 17–19).

References

  • Amsterdam, J., & McHenry, L. (2012). The Paroxetine 352 bipolar trial: A study in medical ghostwriting. International Journal of Risk and Safety in Medicine, 24, 221–231. doi:10.3233/JRS-2012-0571.

  • Anderson, E. (2004). Uses of value judgments in science. Hypatia, 19(Winter), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E. (2005, 2008). Dewey’s moral philosophy. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Dordrecht: Reidel. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/dewey-moral/.

  • Aristotle, (1984). Nicomachean ethics. In J. Barnes (Ed.), The complete works of Aristotle (pp. 1729–1867). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baird, D. (2004). Thing knowledge: A philosophy of scientific instruments. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, B., & Bloor, D. (1982). Relativism, rationalism and the sociology of knowledge. In M. Hollis & S. Lukes (Eds.), Rationality and relativism (pp. 21–47). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berenson, A. (2005). Evidence in Vioxx suits shows intervention by Merck officials. New York Times, April 24.

  • Betz, G. (2013). In defence of the value free ideal. European Journal of Philosophy of Science, 3(2), 20–207. doi:10.1007/s13194-012-0062-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biddle, J. (2007). Lessons from the Vioxx Debacle: What the privatization of science can teach us about social epistemology. Social Epistemology, 21(1), 21–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biddle, J. (2009). Advocates or unencumbered selves? On the role of mill’s political liberalism in Longino’s sociopragmatism. Philosophy of Science, 76(5), 612–623.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, M. (2011). Inquiry and evidence: From the experimenter’s regress to evidence-based policy. Unpublished manuscript. Retrieved August 20, 2012. http://utdallas.academia.edu/MatthewBrown/Papers/300331/Inquiry_and_Evidence_From_the_Experimenters_Regress_to_Evidence-Based_Policy

  • Brown, M. (2012). John Dewey’s logic of science. HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science, 2(2), 258–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, M. (2013a). Review of Philip Kitcher, science in a democratic society. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. Retrieved March 12, 2014. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/29284-science-in-a-democratic-society/.

  • Brown, M. (2013b). The source and status of values for socially responsible science. Philosophical Studies, 163(1), 67–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, M. (2013c). Values in science beyond underdetermination and inductive risk. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 39–829.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callaway, E. (2010). Questions over ghostwriting in drug industry. Nature News Blog. doi:10.1038/news.2010.453. Retrieved August 22, 2011, from http://www.nature.com/news/2010/100907/full/news.2010.453.html.

  • Cartwright, N. (2006). Well-ordered science: Evidence for use. Philosophy of Science, 73(5), 981–990.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1988). Theory of valuation. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), John Dewey: The later works, 1925–1953 (Vol. 13: 1938–1939, pp. 189–251). Southern Illinois University Press: Carbondale and Edwardsville.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2000). Inductive risk and values in science. Philosophy of Science, 67(4), 559–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2009). Science, policy, and the value-free ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2013). The value of cognitive values. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 796–806.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2014). Pure science and the problem of progress. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2014.02.001.

  • Elliott, C. (2004). Pharma goes to the laundry: Public relations and the business of medical education. Hastings Center Report, 34(5), 18–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, Kevin. (2011). Is a little pollution good for you? Incorporating societal values in environmental research. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. (2012). Epistemic and methodological iteration in scientific research. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 43, 82–376. doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2011.12.034.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K., & McKaughan, D. (2009). How values in scientific discovery and pursuit alter theory appraisal. Philosophy of Science, 76(5), 598–611. doi:10.1086/605807.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, C. (2012). Feminist engagement with evolutionary psychology. Hypatia, 27(1), 1–23. Winter.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1993). Against method (3rd ed.). London and New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (1972). Morality as a system of hypothetical imperatives. Philosophical Review, 81(3), 305–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (2001). Dynamics of reason. Stanford: Center for the Study of Language/Information.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fugh-Berman, A. (2010). The Haunting of medical journals: How ghostwriting sold ‘HRT’. PLoS Medicine, 7(9), e1000335. doi:10.1371/journal.pmed.1000335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hicks, D. (2012). Scientific practices and their social context. Phd thesis, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame.

  • Julious, S. (2013). Efficacy and suicidal risk for antidepressants in paediatric and adolescent patients. Statistical Methods in Medical Research, 22(2), 190–218. doi:10.1177/0962280211432210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jureidini, J., McHenry, L., & Mansfield, P. (2008). Clinical trials and drug promotion: Selective reporting of study 329. International Journal of Risk and Safety in Medicine, 20, 73–81. doi:10.3233/JRS-2008-0426.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kindcaid, H., Dupré, J., & Wylie, A. (2007). Value-free science?. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2001). Science, truth, and democracy. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2011). Science in a democratic society. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2003). Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language. Analysis, 63(279), 190–194. doi:10.1111/1467-8284.00419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1977). Objectivity, value judgment, and theory choice. The essential tension (pp. 320–339). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, H. (1999). Is science value free? Values and scientific understanding. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, H. (2005a). On the interplay of the cognitive and the social in scientific practices. Philosophy of Science, 72(5), 88–977.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, H. (2005b). Values and objectivity in science: The current controversy about transgenic crops. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, H. (2013). Rehabilitating neutrality. Philosophical Studies, 163(1), 77–83. doi:10.1007/s11098-012-0074-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, H., & Mariconda, P. R. (2012). The Eagle and the Starlings: Galileo’s argument for the autonomy of science: How pertinent is it today? Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 43(1), 31–122. doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2011.10.012.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ledford, H. (2013). Virtual reality. Nature, 498, 9–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1990). Science as social knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1995). Gender, politics, and the theoretical virtues. Synthese, 104(3), 97–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1996). Cognitive and Non-Cognitive values in science: Rethinking the dichotomy. In L. H. Nelson & J. Nelson (Eds.), Feminism, science, and the philosophy of science (pp. 39–58). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1984). After virtue (2nd ed.). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (2006). Moral relativism, truth, and justification. Selected essays: The task of philosophy (pp. 52–73). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, P. D. (2013). What scientists know is not a function of what scientists know. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 9–840.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McHenry, L. (2009). Ghosts in the machine: Comment on Sismondo. Social Studies of Science, 39(6), 943–947.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McHenry, L., & Jureidini, J. (2008). Industry-sponsored ghostwriting in clinical trial reporting: A case study. Accountability in Research: Policies and Quality Assurance, 15, 152–167. doi:10.1080/08989620802194384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKaughan, D. (2007). Toward a Richard vocabulary for epistemic attitudes: Mapping the cognitive landscape. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Notre Dame.

  • McMullin, E. (1983). Values in science. In P. Asquith & T. Nickles (Eds.), Proceedings of the 1982 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (PSA 1982) (Vol. 2, pp. 3–28). Chicago: Philosophy of Science Association.

  • McMullin, E. (1985). Galilean idealization. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 16(3), 247–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mirowski, P., & Van Horn, R. (2005). The contract research organization and the commercialization of scientific research. Social Studies of Science, 35(4), 48–503. doi:10.1177/0306312705052103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okruhlik, K. (1994). Gender and the biological sciences. Canadian Journal of Philosophy (Supplement), 20, 21–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okruhlik, K. (2004). Logical empiricism, feminism, and Neurath’s auxiliary motive. Hypatia, 19(1), 48–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psaty, B., & Kronmal, R. (2008). Reporting mortality findings in trials of Rofecoxib for Alzheimer disease or cognitive impairment: A case study based on documents from Rofecoxib litigation. Journal of the American Medical Association, 299(15), 1813–1817. doi:10.1001/jama.299.15.1813.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radder, H. (Ed.). (2010). Mertonian values, scientific norms, and the commodification of academic research, Chap. 10. In The commodification of academic research. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

  • Resnik, D. (2010). Financial interests and the norms of academic science, Chap. 4. In Radder (Ed.).

  • Richardson, H. (1994). Practical reasoning about final ends. Cambridge, UK and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rooney, P. (1992). On values in science: Is the epistemic/non-epistemic distinction useful. In D. Hull, M. Forbes, & K. Okruhlik (Eds.) Proceedings of the 1992 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (PSA 1992) (Vol. 2, pp. 13–22). Chicago: Philosophy of Science Association.

  • Rorty, R. (1991). The priority of democracy to philosophy. Objectivity, relativism and truth (pp. 175–195). Cambridge, UK and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, J., Hill, K., Egilman, D., & Krumholz, H. (2008). Guest authorship and ghostwriting in publications related to Rofecoxib: A case study of industry documents from Rofecoxib litigation. Journal of the American Medical Association, 299(15), 1800–1812. doi:10.1001/jama.299.15.1800.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. (2007). Social practices and normativity. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 37(1), 46–56. doi:10.1177/0048393106296542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, M. (1998). Liberalism and the limits of justice (2nd ed.). Cambridge, UK and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schiebinger, L. (1999). Has feminism changed science?. Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sismondo, S. (2009a). Ghosts in the machine: Publication planning in the medical sciences. Social Studies of Science, 39(2), 98–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sismondo, S. (2009). Ghosts in the machine: Reply to McHenry (2009). Social Studies of Science, 39(6), 52–949.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steel, D. (2010). Epistemic values and the argument from inductive risk. Philosophy of Science, 77, 14–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steel, D., & Whyte, K. P. (2012). Environmental justice, values, and scientific expertise. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 22(2), 163–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sung, S. C., Wisniewski, S. R., Balasubramani, G. K., Zisook, S., Kurian, B., Warden, D., et al. (2013). Does early-onset chronic or recurrent major depression impact outcomes with antidepressant medications? A CO-MED trial report. Psychological Medicine, 43(5), 945–960. doi:10.1017/S0033291712001742.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Talisse, R. (2010). An epistemological defense of democracy. Critical Review, 22(2–3), 281–291. doi:10.1080/08913811.2010.508636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuana, N. (2012). Embedding philosophers in the practices of science: Bringing humanities to the sciences. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-012-0171-2.

  • van den Belt, H. (2010). Robert Merton, intellectual property, and open science, Chap. 9. In Radder (Ed.).

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wadman, M. (2011). Paxil study under fire. Nature, 475, 153. doi:10.1038/475153a.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wylie, A. (2001). Doing social science as a feminist: The engendering of archeology. In A. Creager, E. Lunbeck, & L. Schiebinger (Eds.), Feminism in twentieth-century science, technology, and medicine. Women in culture and society (pp. 23–45). Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wylie, A. (2002). Thinking from things: Essays in the philosophy of archaeology. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wylie, A., & Nelson, L. H. (2007). Chap. 3. In H. Kindcaid, J. Dupré, & A. Wylie (Eds.), Coming to terms with the values of science: Insights from feminist science studies scholarship. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Kevin Elliott, Heather Douglas, Charles Pence, Robert Audi, Amelia Hicks, Kenny Boyce, Aaron Segal, Rachael Brown, Kerry McKenzie, and Keizo Matsurbara for comments on earlier versions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel J. Hicks.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hicks, D.J. A new direction for science and values. Synthese 191, 3271–3295 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0447-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0447-9

Keywords

Navigation