Elsevier

Cognition

Volume 125, Issue 3, December 2012, Pages 466-474
Cognition

Do children think that duplicating the body also duplicates the mind?

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2012.07.005Get rights and content

Abstract

Philosophers use hypothetical duplication scenarios to explore intuitions about personal identity. Here we examined 5- to 6-year-olds’ intuitions about the physical properties and memories of a live hamster that is apparently duplicated by a machine. In Study 1, children thought that more of the original’s physical properties than episodic memories were present in the duplicate hamster. In Study 2, children thought that episodic memories of the hamster were less likely to duplicate than events captured by a digital camera. Studies 3 and 4 ruled out lower-level explanations of these effects. Study 5 showed that naming the original hamster further reduced the inferred duplication of memories in the second hamster. Taken together, these studies are consistent with the view that young children think that some mental properties are distinct from physical ones.

Highlights

► Duplication of a hamster is used to investigate intuitions regarding mind and body. ► Children are more likely to infer that physical rather than memories can be copied. ► Episodic memories may be a basis for attributing unique identity to individuals.

Introduction

Philosophers have long been intrigued by perfect duplicates. In The Transfiguration of the Commonplace, Arthur Danto wrote, “I have been obsessed with paired cases where only one member of the couple is an artwork.” (1981, p. 90). An example of this is Marcel Duchamp’s Fountain, an important and much-admired artwork, which Danto imagined paired with a perceptually indistinguishable urinal, an everyday object that has no artistic merit. Or one might compare an original Picasso with a perfect forgery – although the perceptual and microphysical properties of the two objects might be identical, still, they differ greatly in value and (on some analyses) aesthetic merit. Such examples illustrate the limits of physical properties in the categorisation and evaluation of art, and suggest further that beliefs about the works’ history have a particular relevance (see also Bloom, 2010, Hood, 2009).

Consider now the duplication of people – a classic philosopher’s thought experiment used to contrast and develop theories of personal identity and psychological states (Armstrong, 1980, Nozick, 1981, Shoemaker, 1979; see Martin, Barresi, and Giovanelli (1998) for historical review). In one well-known scenario developed by Derek Parfit, Parfit enters a futuristic teletransporter pod that scans his body to record the exact state of all physical matter and then sends this information to Mars, where a duplicate is re-constructed from this information with new matter (Parfit, 1984). Back on Earth, the original Parfit is destroyed. Is the person who now exists on Mars really Parfit? Does he (or it) share the same mental states as the original?

The focus of the experiments reported below is not the metaphysical issues, but rather on our developing folk psychological intuitions. We ask whether, in a Parfit-like scenario, young children will believe that certain mental states will be shared between an original and a duplicate. Will they believe that their bodies will be identical but their minds will not be?

Previous research suggests that, like adults, children appreciate that one can be the same individual despite changes in personal properties – for instance, one can change clothing, cut his hair, and lose some weight and yet still remain the same person (see e.g., Gutheil & Rosengren, 1996). Children know as well that a proper name refers to an individual that has a unique spatiotemporal path and does not extend to an individual of identical appearance in a different location (MacNamara, 1982, Sorrentino, 2001; see also Gutheil, Gelman, Klein, Michos, & Kelaita, 2008). But children have not yet been tested on Parfit-like instances in which an apparent duplicate is not connected to the original through a distinct spatio-temporal path (though see Rips, Blok, and Newman (2006) and Rhemtulla and Hall (2009) for research with adults).

One motivation to ask this question is to explore the claim that people are natural Cartesian dualists. It is sometimes argued that, prior to exposure to scientific education, children assume that mental properties are distinct from physical ones (Bering and Bjorklund, 2004, Bloom, 2004, Cohen, 2007, Johnson and Wellman, 1982). The duplication scenario can explore this. If psychological states emerge from (supervene upon) physical brain states, then the duplicate should have all the same mental states as the original. However, if one is a Cartesian dualist, believing that the experiencing self is distinct from the body, then a physically identical duplicate might have different mental states.

Rather than a strictly verbal thought experiment, we tested children by showing them actual duplication. In previous research, we found that young children accept the possibility of duplication when presented with a scientific looking machine that can apparently copy real objects, such as toys (Hood & Bloom, 2008). We use this method here to duplicate live hamsters. Unlike the Parfit scenario, we did not destroy (or pretend to destroy) the original hamster, in part because of concerns about children’s sensibilities and in part because the extent to which children attribute physical and mental properties to the original serves as a baseline with which to compare their attribution to the duplicate.

We focus on 5- and 6-year-olds because we found in pilot studies that younger children often perseverated on a single response and failed control questions while older children were less credulous of the duplicating machine. Further, this age group overlaps with studies that use alternative methods to explore young children’s understanding of bodies and minds (e.g., Choe, Keil, & Bloom, 2012, Gottfried et al., 1999, Johnson, 1990).

We restricted the investigation of mental states to knowledge states based on episodic memories. From a methodological perspective, this allowed us to experimentally manipulate the presence or absence of mental states in a way that was easily understood by children; it also enabled us to compare mental states of an animal with the internal states of a camera.

We also focused on episodic memory because it may have a particular relevance to personal identity. According to Locke’s (1690/1975, chap. xxvii) theory of personal identity, individuality is defined in terms of the continuity of memories. Personal identity may also involve other mental states such as preferences, attitudes, and emotions, but to a lesser extent. For example, two very different individuals can both like vanilla ice-cream or believe in ghosts and a single individual can change her mind about ice-cream and ghosts without changing her identity. In contrast, experiencing an event or being supplied with exclusive knowledge induces novel epistemic mental states that are not typically shared with others who were not present at the induction. Note also that our focus on epistemic states is similar to the work of Gutheil and colleagues (Gutheil et al., 2008), who asked children whether two identical looking Winnie-the-Pooh dolls shared the same knowledge state that was supplied to only one doll. Similarly, in the experiments reported here, we introduced specific events that we could ensure were understood by the children to constitute memories for the original hamster.

Section snippets

Participants

Twenty-three second-year primary schoolchildren (12 males, 11 females, mean age = 72 months, range 66–78 months) were tested. No children were excluded. In this experiment and all that follow, all children were tested individually in a quiet room at their school after parents had provided their consent. Each child had English as their first language and normal or corrected-to-normal vision.

Familiarisation

Each session began with the child drawing a picture and signing the drawing with their name. Children were

Experiment 2

One interpretation of the above results is that it reflects a tendency towards a dualist conception of animate beings. This raises the question as to whether children would draw the same dissociation between memories and invisible recordings on a digital camera.

Experiment 3

Experiments 1 and 2 suggest that memories are more resistant to duplication than physical properties. However, an alternative explanation for the dissociations is that physical properties were based on testimony of the experimenter whereas the memories where based on events that the child observed. That is, the child was told that Hamster 1 had a marble in his stomach, a missing tooth and a blue heart but actually witnessed the hamster seeing the drawing, hearing their name and being tickled.

Experiment 4

Another alternative is that young children conceive of physical attributes as permanent and mental attributes as transient. If this is the case then the dissociations between mental and physical states observed in all of the previous experiments may have resulted because children think that permanent states will be replicated while transient states will not, and might not reflect a distinction between the physical and the psychological. To examine this possibility, we repeated the study with

Experiment 5

Experiment 5 was a modified replication of Experiment 1 except that we gave the original hamster a proper name. The naming of the hamster was motivated by the philosophical analysis in which proper names are rigid designators of unique identity, tracing identity over both real and hypothesised space and time (e.g., Kripke, 1980). Young children are aware that proper names refer to distinct individuals, not categories (e.g., Gelman and Taylor, 1984, Hall et al., 2001, Katz et al., 1974,

General discussion

Do children who accept the duplication of physical properties reject the duplication of minds? To test this, we used a duplication paradigm similar to philosophical thought experiments to investigate children’s intuitions about whether it is possible to duplicate memories as well as unseen physical properties. In Experiment 1, children thought more physical than memory states were present in an apparently copied hamster. In Experiment 2, children again thought more physical properties than

Acknowledgements

This work was supported by Grants to the first author from the Leverhulme Trust, UK, the Bial Foundation, Portugal and the Perrott-Warwick Trust, UK.

References (34)

  • D. Davidson

    Knowing one’s own mind

    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association

    (1987)
  • S.A. Gelman

    The essential child: Origins of essentialism in everyday thought

    (2003)
  • S.A. Gelman et al.

    How two-year-old children interpret proper and common names for unfamiliar objects

    Child Development

    (1984)
  • A. Gopnik et al.

    Children’s understanding of representational change and its relation to the understanding of false belief and the appearance–reality distinction

    Child Development

    (1988)
  • C.J. Guardo et al.

    Development of a sense of self-identity in children

    Child Development

    (1971)
  • G. Gutheil et al.

    A rose by any other name: Preschoolers’ understanding of individual identity across name and appearance change

    British Journal of Developmental Psychology

    (1996)
  • D.G. Hall et al.

    Young children’s use of syntactic cues to learn descriptive proper names

    Developmental Psychology

    (2001)
  • Cited by (41)

    • On the matter of essence

      2021, Cognition
      Citation Excerpt :

      This schism is, of course, the telltale sign of psychological dualism—another intuitive principle that is widely documented in laypeople (Bloom, 2004). People, indeed, tend to view the mind as immaterial, distinct from the physical body, and this is the case for adults (Chudek, McNamara, Birch, Bloom, & Henrich, 2018; Forstmann & Burgmer, 2015; Forstmann, Burgmer, & Mussweiler, 2012; Stanovich, 1989; Watson-Jones, Busch, Harris, & Legare, 2017), children (Chudek et al., 2018; Hood, Gjersoe, & Bloom, 2012), and possibly, infants (Kuhlmeier, Bloom, & Wynn, 2004; Spelke, Phillips, & Woodward, 1995). Dualism not only explains why psychological traits are treated differently from physical properties of the body, it can further account for the differentiation between distinct psychological traits.

    • Intuitions about personal identity are rooted in essentialist thinking across development

      2019, Cognition
      Citation Excerpt :

      From this perspective, judgments of personal identity may be unduly influenced by a cognitive bias that should not, in principle, play a role in generating these judgments. Although others have speculated about a link between essentialist thinking and concepts of personal identity before (e.g., Hood, Gjersoe, & Bloom, 2012; Newman, Bartels, & Smith, 2014), this hypothesis has not yet been tested. Thus, our goal here is to investigate whether essentialist thinking is indeed part of the reason why people think that a person’s identity depends on the specific bits of matter of which they are composed.

    • A free will needs a free mind: Belief in substance dualism and reductive physicalism differentially predict belief in free will and determinism

      2018, Consciousness and Cognition
      Citation Excerpt :

      While the former may be considered side-effects of more fundamental cognitive processes and experiences, the latter seem manifestations of culturally-shared worldviews that are themselves potentially informed by shared intuitions (a constructionist view), as well as by acquired scientific knowledge (Forstmann & Burgmer, 2017). Specifically, according to theoretical and empirical contributions in this domain (e.g., Bloom, 2004; Bering, 2006; Forstmann & Burgmer, 2015) people seem to intuitively think of minds and bodies as two distinct entities, a fact that already becomes evident in early childhood (Bering & Bjorklund, 2004; Hood, Gjersoe, & Bloom, 2012). As a result, some scholars refer to human beings as natural-born dualists (Bloom, 2004), intuitive mind-body dualists (Forstmann & Burgmer, 2015), or implicit theists (Uhlmann, Poelhlman, & Bargh, 2008).

    • How to Tell a Dualist?

      2023, Cognitive Science
    View all citing articles on Scopus
    View full text