Skip to main content
Log in

Having an interpretation

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

What the music I love expresses to me, is not thought too indefinite to put into words, but on the contrary, too definite.

Abstract

I investigate what it means to have an interpretation of our language, how we manage to bestow a determinate interpretation to our utterances, and to which extent our interpretation of the world is determinate. All this is done in dialogue with van Fraassen’s insightful discussion of Putnam’s model-theoretic argument and of scientific structuralism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The most important ones are van Fraassen (1997a, b).

  2. See also van Fraassen (1997a, p. 21; 1997b, p. 91).

  3. None of this prevents us to partially capture, by means of axioms, our interpretation of our language.

  4. The example concerns the distinction between the existence of a coordinate system for the Euclidean plane and our ability to coordinatize the plane.

  5. I realise that there are really a number of reference fixing questions. Space does not permit me to discuss them separately or even to distinguish between them here.

  6. In defence of Putnam, some commentators have said that Putnam should have said that the only notion of causality that we can make sense of is so overdetermined that it is powerless as a reference fixer, or that the model-theoretic argument can be formulated in such a way that the causal theory of reference cannot be invoked as a way out (Douven 1999). I have pointed out my reservations about Douven’s reconstruction in Horsten (2001 p. 130).

  7. There an in rebus structuralism is articulated according to which reference to natural numbers can be seen as multiple reference to concrete objects belonging to (concrete) notation systems.

  8. I do not mean to suggest that one day there was a gathering of scientists in which the extension of ‘copper’ was fixed in this way.

  9. I shall not discuss Worrall’s Kantian epistemological structuralism here.

  10. Ladyman appears to be somewhat troubled by this question. See Ladyman (2007, pp. 39–40).

  11. For a comparison between ontological structuralism and ante rem structuralism in the philosophy of mathematics, see Ladyman (2007).

References

  • Douven, I. (1999). Putnam’s model-theoretic argument reconstructed. Journal of Philosophy, 96, 479–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halbach, V., & Horsten, L. (2005). Computational structuralism. Philosophia Mathematica, 13, 174–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horsten, L. (2001). On our ability to fix intended structures. In T. Derksen (Ed.), Moving ahead: Philosophy of mind and realism (pp. 121–134). Nijmegen: Dutch University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (1998). What is structural realism? Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 409–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2007). On the identity and diversity of objects in a structure. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 81, 23–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1984). Putnam’s paradox. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 62, 221–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning’. In Mind, language and reality. Philosophical papers (Vol. 2, pp. 215–271). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Putnam, H. (1978). Realism and reason. In Meaning and the moral sciences (pp. 123–140). London: Routledge.

  • van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1997a). Putnam’s paradox: Metaphysical realism revamped and evaded. Noûs, 31, 17–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1997b). Elgin on Lewis’s Putnam’s paradox. Journal of Philosophy, 94, 85–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (2006). Structure: Its shadow and substance. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57, 275–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (2007). Structuralism(s) about science: Some common problems. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 81, 45–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (2008). Scientific representation: Paradoxes of perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Igor Douven and to my colleagues in Bristol for helpful discussions. The research for this project was supported by an AHRC project on Foundations of Structuralism (AH/H001670/1).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Leon Horsten.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Horsten, L. Having an interpretation. Philos Stud 150, 449–459 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9548-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9548-6

Keywords

Navigation