Skip to main content
Log in

Symbols and Computation A Critique of the Computational Theory of Mind

  • Published:
Minds and Machines Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Over the past several decades, the philosophical community has witnessed the emergence of an important new paradigm for understanding the mind.1 The paradigm is that of machine computation, and its influence has been felt not only in philosophy, but also in all of the empirical disciplines devoted to the study of cognition. Of the several strategies for applying the resources provided by computer and cognitive science to the philosophy of mind, the one that has gained the most attention from philosophers has been the ‘Computational Theory of Mind’ (CTM). CTM was first articulated by Hilary Putnam (1960, 1961), but finds perhaps its most consistent and enduring advocate in Jerry Fodor (1975, 1980, 1981, 1987, 1990, 1994). It is this theory, and not any broader interpretations of what it would be for the mind to be a computer, that I wish to address in this paper. What I shall argue here is that the notion of ‘symbolic representation’ employed by CTM is fundamentally unsuited to providing an explanation of the intentionality of mental states (a major goal of CTM), and that this result undercuts a second major goal of CTM, sometimes refered to as the ‘vindication of intentional psychology.’ This line of argument is related to the discussions of ‘derived intentionality’ by Searle (1980, 1983, 1984) and Sayre (1986, 1987). But whereas those discussions seem to be concerned with the causal dependence of familiar sorts of symbolic representation upon meaning-bestowing acts, my claim is rather that there is not one but several notions of ‘meaning’ to be had, and that the notions that are applicable to symbols are conceptually dependent upon the notion that is applicable to mental states in the fashion that Aristotle refered to as paronymy. That is, an analysis of the notions of ‘meaning’ applicable to symbols reveals that they contain presuppositions about meaningful mental states, much as Aristotle's analysis of the sense of ‘healthy’ that is applied to foods reveals that it means ‘conducive to having a healthy body,’ and hence any attempt to explain ‘mental semantics’ in terms of the semantics of symbols is doomed to circularity and regress. I shall argue, however, that this does not have the consequence that computationalism is bankrupt as a paradigm for cognitive science, as it is possible to reconstruct CTM in a fashion that avoids these difficulties and makes it a viable research framework for psychology, albeit at the cost of losing its claims to explain intentionality and to vindicate intentional psychology. I have argued elsewhere (Horst, 1996) that local special sciences such as psychology do not require vindication in the form of demonstrating their reducibility to more fundamental theories, and hence failure to make good on these philosophical promises need not compromise the broad range of work in empirical cognitive science motivated by the computer paradigm in ways that do not depend on these problematic treatments of symbols.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Block, N. (1986), ‘Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology’, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10, pp. 615–678.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1983), The Nature of Psychological Explanation, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins R. (1989), Meaning and Mental Representation, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1987), ‘Evolution, Error, and Intentionality’, in D. Dennett, ed., The Intentional Stance, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981), Knowledge and the Flow of Information, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1986), ‘Misrepresentation’, in R. Bodgan, ed., Belief, Oxford University Press.

  • Dretske, F. (1988), Explaining Behavior, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1978), ‘Mental Representation’, Erkentniss 13, pp. 9–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1975), The Language of Thought, New York: Thomas Crowell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1980), ‘Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Science’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1980), pp. 63–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1981), Representations, Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1987), Psychosemantics, Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1990), A Theory of Content and Other Essays, Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books, MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1994), The Elm and the Expert, Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books, MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J, ed. (1981), Mind Design, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horst, S. (1990), Symbols, Computation and Intentionality: A Critique of the Computational Theory of Mind. Doctoral Dissertation, University of Notre Dame.

  • Horst, S. (1992), ‘Notions of ‘Representation’ and the Diverging Interests of Philosophy and Empirical Science’, Proceedings of the 1992 Conference on Representation at SUNY Buffalo.

  • Horst, S. (1996), Symbols, Computation and Intentionality: A Critique of the Computational Theory of Mind. Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loar, B. ‘Conceptual Role and Truth Conditions’, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23, pp. 272–283.

  • Millikan, R. (1984), Language, Thought and other Biological Categories, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1986), ‘Thoughts Without Laws: Cognitive Science Without Content’, Philosophical Review 95, pp. 47–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (1985), ‘Representation and Explanation’, Philosophy of Science 51, pp. 550–572.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1960), ‘Minds and Machines’, in S. Hook, ed., Dimensions of Mind, New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, S. (1961), ‘Brains and Behavior’, originally read as part of the program of the American Association for the Advancement of Science, Section L, December, 1961, printed in N. Block, ed., Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1980), ‘Computation and Cognition: Issues in the Foundation of Cognitive Science’, The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3, pp. 111–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sayre, K. (1986), ‘Intentionality and Information Processing’ Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9, No. 1 (1986).

  • Sayre, K. (1987), ‘Cognitive Science and the Problem of Semantic Content’, Synthese 70, pp. 247–269.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1980), ‘Minds, Brains and Programs’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3, pp. 417–424.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1983), Intentionality, Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1984), Minds, Brains and Science, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (1972), Meaning, Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1983), From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Horst, S. Symbols and Computation A Critique of the Computational Theory of Mind. Minds and Machines 9, 347–381 (1999). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1008351818306

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1008351818306

Keywords

Navigation