Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-4hhp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-08T08:17:42.771Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Prospects for Peircean Truth

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Andrew Howat*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, California State University, 800 N State College Blvd, Fullerton, CA92831, USA

Abstract

Peircean Truth (PT) is the view that truth is in some sense epistemically constrained, constrained that is by what we would, if we inquired long enough and well enough, eventually come to believe. Contemporary Peirceans offer various different formulations of the view, which can make it difficult, particularly for critics, to see exactly how PT differs from popular alternatives such as correspondence theories or deflationism. This article, therefore, considers four possible formulations of PT, and sets out the different objections and challenges they each face and their relationships with one another. I focus upon the question of what, if anything, PT has to say about the property of truth.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Austin, J. L. 1955. How to Do Things with Words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bar-On, D., and Simmons, K.. 2007. “The Use of Force Against Deflationism: Assertion and Truth.” In Truth and Speech Acts: Studies in the Philosophy of Language, edited by Greimann, D., and Siegwart, G., 6189. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Battaly, H. 2008. “Review of ‘Epistemic Logic: A Survey of the Logic of Knowledge’.” Mind 117 (465): 205210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baz, A. 2012a. “Must Philosophers Rely on Intuitions?Journal of Philosophy 109 (4): 316337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baz, A. 2012b. When Words Are Called For: A Defense of Ordinary Language Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blackburn, S. 2011. “Pragmatism in Philosophy: The Hidden Alternative.” Philosophic Exchange 41 (1): 113.Google Scholar
Brandom, R. 1987 (1988). “Pragmatism, Phenomenalism, and Truth Talk.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12 (1): 7593.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edwards, D. 2013. “Truth as a Substantive Property.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91 (2): 279294. 10.1080/00048402.2012.686514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feltz, A., and Cokely, E. T.. 2011. “The Philosophical Personality Argument.” Philosophical Studies 161 (2): 227246.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitch, F. (1963) 2009. “A Logical Analysis of Some Value Concepts.” The Journal of Symbolic Logic 28: 135142. Reprinted in Salerno (ed.), 21–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grover, D., Camp, J., and Belnap, N.. 1975. “A Prosentential Theory of Truth.” Philosophical Studies 27 (2): 73125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haack, S. 1982. “Descartes, Peirce and the Cognitive Community.” The Monist 65 (2): 156181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hale, B. 1997. “Realism and Its Oppositions.” In A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, edited by Hale, B., and Wright, C., 271308. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hart, W. D., and McGinn, C.. 1976. “Knowledge and Necessity.” Journal of Philosophical Logic 5: 205208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hilgevoord, J. 2006. “The Uncertainty Principle.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qt-uncertainty/.Google Scholar
Hookway, C. J. 2002. Truth, Rationality and Pragmatism: Themes from Peirce. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hookway, C. J. 2004. “Truth, Reality and Convergence.” In The Cambridge Companion to Peirce, edited by Misak, C., 127149. Cambridge: University PressCambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hookway, C. J. 2012. The Pragmatic Maxim: Essays on Peirce and Pragmatism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howat, A. 2011. “Shallow Versus Deep Response-Dependence.” Philosophical Studies 156 (2): 155172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howat, A. 2013. “Regulative Assumptions, Hinge Propositions and the Peircean Conception of Truth.” Erkenntnis 78 (2): 451468.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langton, R. 1993. “Speech Acts and Unspeakable Acts.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 22 (4): 293330.Google Scholar
Laraudogoitia, J. P. 2009. “Supertasks.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Zalta, Edward N.. Fall 2013 Edition. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/spacetime-supertasks/.Google Scholar
Legg, C. 2008a. “Argument-Forms Which Turn Invalid Over Infinite Domains: Physicalism as Supertask?Contemporary Pragmatism 5 (1): 111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Legg, C. 2008b. “Making It Explicit and Clear: From ‘Strong’ to ‘Hyper’- Inferentialism in Brandom and Peirce.” Metaphilosophy 39 (1): 105123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Legg, C. 2014. “Charles Peirce’s Limit Concept of Truth.” Philosophy Compass 9 (3): 204213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lynch, M. P. 2010. Truth as One and Many. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mayorga, R. M. P. T. 2007. From Realism to “Realicism”: The Metaphysics of Charles Sanders Peirce. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Misak, C. J. 2004. Truth and the End of Inquiry: A Peircean Account of Truth. Expanded Paperback EditionOxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Misak, C. J. 2007. “Pragmatism and Deflationism.” In New Pragmatists, edited by Misak, C. J., 6890. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Murphey, M. G. 1993. The Development of Peirce’s Philosophy. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. 1877. “The Fixation of Belief.” Popular Science Monthly 12 (November): 115.Google Scholar
Peirce, C. S. 1878. “How to Make Our Ideas Clear.” Popular Science Monthly 12 (January): 286302.Google Scholar
Price, H. 2003. “Truth as Convenient Friction.” The Journal of Philosophy 100 (4): 167190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Price, H. 2010. “One cheer for representationalism?” In The Philosophy of Richard Rorty, edited by Auxier, R.. Vol. XXXII, 269289. Chicago, IL: Open Court, Library of Living Philosophers.Google Scholar
Price, H. 2011. Naturalism Without Mirrors. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rescher, N. 2005. Epistemic Logic. Pittsburgh, PA: Pittsburgh University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reynolds, A. 2002. Peirce’s Scientific Metaphysics: The Philosophy of Chance, Law, and Evolution. Nashville, TN: Vanderbilt University Press.Google Scholar
Rochberg-Halton, E. 1986. Meaning and Modernity. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
Skagestad, P. 1981. The Road of Inquiry, Charles Peirce’s Pragmatic Realism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Stich, S. P. 1990. The Fragmentation of Reason: Preface to a Pragmatic Theory of Cognitive Evaluation. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Stoljar, D., and Damnjanovic, N.. 2013. “The Deflationary Theory of Truth.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Zalta, Edward N.. Fall 2013 Edition. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/truth-deflationary/.Google Scholar
Tiercelin, C. 1997. “Peirce on Norms, Evolution and Knowledge.” Transactions of the Charles Sanders Peirce Society 33 (1): 3558.Google Scholar
Wiggins, D. 2004. “Reflections on Inquiry and Truth Arising from Peirce’s Method for the Fixation of Belief.” In The Cambridge Companion to Peirce, edited by Misak, C. J., 87126. Cambridge: University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, C. 1992. Truth and Objectivity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wright, C. 2001. “Minimalism, Deflationism, Pragmatism, Pluralism.” In The Nature of Truth, edited by Lynch, M. P., 751787. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Wright, C. D. 2012. “Is Pluralism About Truth Inherently Unstable?Philosophical Studies 159 (1): 89105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar