Skip to main content
Log in

What does the character of medicine as a social practice imply for professional conscientious objection?

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The dispute over professional conscientious objection presumes a picture of medicine as a practice governed by rules. This rule-based conception of medical practice is identifiable with John Rawls’s conception of social practices. This conception does not capture the character of medical practice as experienced by practitioners, for whom it is a sensibility or “form of life” rather than rules. Moreover, the sensibility of medical practice as experienced by physicians is at best neutral, and at worst hostile, to the demands of those who would override physician conscientious objection to the provision of currently contested services. That being so, calls for overriding physician conscientious objection are much more demanding of the medical profession than they appear in light of Rawls’s view. As such overriding may entail the forcible transformation of medicine’s form of life, the author contends that it would be more prudent to provide contested services by circumventing the medical profession than by compelling it.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Robert Card and Mark Wicclair respectively rely on tests of reason and conformity to core professional obligations as criteria for evaluating conscientious objections. See [5] and [6, ch. 3].

  2. The following discussion, as will be evident, is deeply indebted to Michael Thompson’s explication of Rawls in [14, ch. 10].

  3. As has been pointed out by, among others, H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr. in [17, pp. 320–325].

  4. Practical holism is the view that while understanding “involves explicit beliefs and hypotheses, these can only be meaningful in specific contexts and against a background of shared practices.” Stern [18, p. 188] quoting Hubert Dreyfus.

  5. Wittgenstein [12, pp. 185–219]. The central rule following passages in [12] are pp. 185–242. See also [13, p. 3].

  6. See Thompson [14, ch. 11] for a defense of the suggestion that the unity of practices is analogous to that of a life form.

  7. As per William Osler: “To study the phenomena of disease without books is to sail an uncharted sea, while to study books without patients is not to go to sea at all” in [23, p. 220].

  8. For contemporary defenses of the distinctiveness of knowing how from knowing that and of the indispensability of knowing how for practical action, see P.M.S. Hacker [24, ch. 4] and David Wiggins [25].

  9. See [26]; the ensuing discussion is indebted to my more extensive treatment of these issues in [27].

  10. That is, in the case of the two most controversial services, abortion and physician-assisted death.

  11. In 2005, 80% of US abortions were performed by the 22% of abortion providers who did 1000 or more abortions that year [34, p. 12, Table 4].

  12. Jonathan Imber documented this phenomenon in his important study [36].

  13. Surveys up to the year 2000 summarized by Emanuel suggested that while two-thirds of the American public supported PAS, surveys of physicians rarely revealed support as high as 50% and willingness to participate was much lower. Oncologists were less willing to participate than were other physicians [37]. Recent Medscape surveys put physician support for the availability of PAS at 54% [38]. Support of PAS by medical students has been higher in some surveys, e.g., [39]. A 2003 survey of members of Britain’s Association for Palliative Medicine revealed 92.6% of members to be opposed to legalization of PAS [40].

  14. For reasons of space and focus, the constraint against killing patients professed by American medical organizations and the majority of American physicians, which I contend is often experienced as a deontological constraint, an aspect of the sensibility of medical practice, cannot be defended here. It is enough for my purposes to note that its validity is an open question.

References

  1. Curlin, Farr A., Ryan E. Lawrence, Marshall H. Chin, and John D. Lantos. 2007. Religion, conscience, and controversial clinical practices. New England Journal of Medicine 356: 593–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists. 2013. Publications November 2013. Obstetrics and Gynecology 122: 1121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Pellegrino, Edmund D. 2002. The physician’s conscience, conscience clauses, and religious belief: A Catholic perspective. Fordham Urban Law Journal 30: 221–244.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Rhodes, Rosamond. 2006. The ethical standard of care. American Journal of Bioethics 6: 76–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Card, Robert F. 2014. Reasonability and conscientious objection in medicine: A reply to Marsh and an elaboration of the reason-giving requirement. Bioethics 28: 320–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Wicclair, Mark R. 2011. Conscientious objection in health care. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  7. Savulescu, Julian. 2006. Conscientious objection in medicine. BMJ 332: 294–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Lynch, Holly Fernandez. 2008. Conflicts of conscience in health care. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  9. Charo, R.Alta. 2005. The celestial fire of conscience—Refusing to deliver medical care. New England Journal of Medicine 352: 2471–2473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Dresser, Rebecca. 2005. Professionals, conformity, and conscience. Hastings Center Report 35: 9–10.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Rawls, John. 1955. Two concepts of rules. Philosophical Review 64: 3–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1953. Philosophical investigations. London: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  13. McDowell, John. 1998. Noncognitivism and rule-following. In Mind, value and reality,” ed. John McDowell, ch. 10. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  14. Thompson, Michael. 2008. Life and action. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  15. Rawls, John. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Brock, Dan. 2008. Conscientious refusal by physicians and pharmacists: Who is obligated to do what, and why? Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 29: 187–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr. 2010. Moral obligation after the death of God: Critical reflections on concerns from Immanuel Kant, G.W.F. Hegel, and Elizabeth Anscombe. Social Philosophy and Policy 27: 317–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Stern, David. 2003. The practical turn. In The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of the social sciences, ed. Stephen Turner and Paul Roth, ch. 8. London: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

  19. Ryle, Gilbert. 1949. The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Searle, John. 1983. Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  21. Dreyfus, Hubert. 2005. Overcoming the myth of the mental: How philosophers can profit from the phenomenology of every day expertise. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 79: 47–65.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Bourdieu, Pierre. 1977. Outline of a theory of practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  23. Osler, William. 2013. Aequanimitas. London: Forgotten Books.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Hacker, P.M.S. 2013. The intellectual powers: A study of human nature. London: Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  25. Wiggins, David. 2012. Practical knowledge: Knowing how to and knowing that. Mind 121: 97–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Project of the ABIM Fopundation, ACP-ASIM foundation and European Federation of Internal Medicine. 2002. Medical professionalism in the new millennium: A physician’s charter. Annals of Internal Medicine 136: 243–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Huddle, Thomas S. 2016. Putting patient autonomy in its proper place: Professional norm-guided medical decision making. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 26: 457–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Dellapenna, Joseph. 2005. Dispelling the myths of abortion history. Durham: Carolina Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  29. MacKay, H. Trent, and Andrea Phillips MacKay. 1995. Abortion training in obstetrics and gynecology residency programs in the United States. Family Planning Perspectives 27: 112–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Jackson, Courtney B., and Angel M. Foster. 2012. Ob/gyn training in abortion care: Results from a national survey. Contraception 86: 407–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Shotorbani, Solmaz, Frederick Zimmerman, Janice Bell, Deborah Ward, and Nassim Assefi. 2004. Attitudes and intentions of future health care providers toward abortion provision. Perspectives on Sexual and Reproductive Health 36: 58–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Allen, R.H., C. Raker, J. Steinauer, K.L. Eastwood, J.E. Kacmar, and L.A. Boardman. 2010. Future abortion provision among US graduating obstetrics and gynecology residents, 2004. Contraception 81: 531–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Stulberg, Debra B., Annie Dude, Irma Dahlquist, and Farr Curlin. 2011. Abortion provision among practicing obstetrician-gynecologists. Obstetrics and Gynecology 118: 609–614.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Jones, Rachel K., Mia Zolna, Stanley Henshaw, and Lawrence Finer. 2008. Abortion in the United States: Incidence and access to services, 2005. Perspectives on Sexual and Reproductive Health 40: 6–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Freedman, Lori, Uta Landy, Philip Darney, and Jody Steinauer. 2010. Obstacles to the integration of abortion into obstetrics and gynecology practice. Perspectives on Sexual and Reproductive Health 42: 146–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Imber, Jonathan. 1986. Abortion and the private practice of medicine. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Emanuel, Ezekiel J. 2002. Euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide: A review of the empirical data from the United States. Archives of Internal Medicine 162: 142–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Kane, Leslie. 2014. Medscape ethics report 2014, part 1: Life, death, and pain. http://www.medscape.com/features/slideshow/public/ethics2014-part1#2. Accessed February 8, 2016.

  39. Mangus, Richard S., Albert Dipiero, and Claire Hawkins. 1999. Medical students’ attitudes toward physician-assisted suicide. JAMA 282: 2080–2081.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Select Committee on Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill. 2003. Survey of APM members views on euthanasia/physician assisted suicide. Minutes of evidence. https://publications.parliament.uk/pa/ld200405/ldselect/ldasdy/86/4102113.htm. Accessed February 8, 2016.

  41. Imber, Jonathan B. 1990. Abortion policy and medical practice. Society 27(5): 27–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas S. Huddle.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Huddle, T.S. What does the character of medicine as a social practice imply for professional conscientious objection?. Theor Med Bioeth 38, 429–445 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-017-9426-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-017-9426-8

Keywords

Navigation