Skip to main content
Log in

Serious theories and skeptical theories: Why you are probably not a brain in a vat

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Skeptical hypotheses such as the brain-in-a-vat hypothesis provide extremely poor explanations for our sensory experiences. Because these scenarios accommodate virtually any possible set of evidence, the probability of any given set of evidence on the skeptical scenario is near zero; hence, on Bayesian grounds, the scenario is not well supported by the evidence. By contrast, serious theories make reasonably specific predictions about the evidence and are then well supported when these predictions are satisfied.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a brain-in-a-vat scenario, see Pollock and Cruz (1999, pp. 2–5). For the deceiving God scenario, see Descartes (1984, p. 14).

  2. How should the skeptic understand the notion of “prediction” here? One interpretation is entailment: the BIV scenario could be described such that it just entails that one has the sort of experiences one in fact has. A more flexible interpretation (which leaves both premises 4 and 5 plausible) would be probabilistic: H predicts E provided that P(E|H) > P(E).

  3. For a sample of approaches, see Putnam (1981), Vogel (1990), Dretske (1981), Klein (1995). In Huemer (2001a, pp. 388–389), I provide grounds for rejecting premise 5.

  4. For a brief, early defense of this approach, see BonJour (1985, pp. 183–185). Note that my present defense of the approach does not indicate an abandonment of the direct realist response to skepticism presented in my earlier work (Huemer 2000, 2001b, pp. 181–191); rather, I believe the unsoundness of the skeptical argument is overdetermined.

  5. Keynes (1921), Carnap (1962), Jaynes (2003), Fumerton (2004), Huemer (2009).

  6. The program assigned a random HSV combination to each pixel, from among 16.7 million possibilities. My computer is unable to display 50 of these per second, but a slide show playing ten images per second shows no detectable patterns. The viewer can tell that the image is changing, but one cannot recognize any specific image when it is repeated.

  7. In Huemer (2009), I argue that when possible, the Principle of Indifference should be applied at a more explanatorily basic level, rather than a more superficial level.

  8. Or perhaps the low a priori probability would merely be a symptom of our having justification for rejecting the proposition, with the considerations that explain why the a priori probability is so low constituting the justification. This distinction is immaterial for present purposes, so I shall hereafter elide the distinction.

  9. I thank Daniel Singer for a version of this objection.

  10. Cf. Vogel’s (2010, pp. 416–417) objection to BonJour.

  11. Ramsey (1931, pp. 160–167) and Gillies (2000, pp. 52–53) reject the notion, while Fumerton (1995, p. 218) and Beebe (2009, pp. 628–632) express doubts.

  12. Huemer (2016).

  13. For another argument for this conclusion, based on probability theory, see Huemer (2009, pp. 26–29).

  14. This premise, the “Principle of Inferential Justification,” has been defended by several epistemologists, including Fumerton (1995, p. 36) and Huemer (2016).

  15. For explanation, see Huemer (2009, pp. 10–13).

  16. Newton (1999).

  17. For a brief explanation of the competing accounts of planetary motion, especially retrograde motion, see Smith (2013).

  18. Hume (1975), section IV; Mackie (1977).

References

  • Beebe, J. (2009). The abductivist reply to skepticism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79, 605–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1962). Logical foundations of probability (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1984). Meditations on first philosophy. In J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, & D. Murdoch (Eds.), The philosophical writings of Descartes (Vol. 2). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). The pragmatic dimension of knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 40, 363–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (1995). Metaepistemology and skepticism. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (2004). Epistemic probability. Philosophical Issues, Epistemology, 14, 149–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, D. (2000). Philosophical theories of probability. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2000). Direct realism and the brain-in-a-vat argument. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 61, 397–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2001a). The problem of defeasible justification. Erkenntnis, 54, 375–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2001b). Skepticism and the Veil of Perception. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2009). Explanationist aid for the theory of inductive logic. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60, 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2016). Inferential appearances. In B. Coppenger & M. Bergmann (Eds.), Intellectual assurance: Essays on traditional epistemic internalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press (forthcoming).

  • Hume, D. (1975). Enquiry concerning human understanding. In L. A. Selby-Bigge & P. H. Nidditch (Eds.), Enquiries concerning human understanding and concerning the principles of morals (3rd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Originally published 1748).

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaynes, E. T. (2003). Probability theory: The logic of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J. (1921). A treatise on probability. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1995). Skepticism and closure: Why the evil genius argument fails. Philosophical Topics, 23, 213–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I. (1999). The principia: Mathematical principles of natural philosophy. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. (Originally published 1787).

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J., & Cruz, J. (1999). Contemporary theories of knowledge. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1981). Brains in a vat. In Reason, truth, and history (pp. 1–21). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Ramsey, F. (1931). Truth and probability. In R. B. Braithwaite (Ed.), The foundations of mathematics and other logical essays (pp. 156–198). London: Kegan, Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, S. (2013). Retrograde motion. http://www.lasalle.edu/~smithsc/Astronomy/retrograd.html. Accessed October 10, 2013.

  • Vogel, J. (1990). Cartesian skepticism and inference to the best explanation. Journal of Philosophy, 87, 658–666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, J. (2010). BonJour on explanation and skepticism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 41, 413–421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Huemer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Huemer, M. Serious theories and skeptical theories: Why you are probably not a brain in a vat. Philos Stud 173, 1031–1052 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0539-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0539-5

Keywords

Navigation