Skip to main content
Log in

Introduction: the plurality of modeling

  • Introduction
  • Published:
History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Philosophers of science have recently focused on the scientific activity of modeling phenomena, and explicated several of its properties, as well as the activities embedded into it. A first approach to modeling has been elaborated in terms of representing a target system: yet other epistemic functions, such as producing data or detecting phenomena, are at least as relevant. Additional useful distinctions have emerged, such as the one between phenomenological and mechanistic models. In biological sciences, besides mathematical models, models now come in three forms: in vivo, in vitro and in silico. Each has been investigated separately, and many specific problems they raised have been laid out. Another relevant distinction is disciplinary: do models differ in significant ways according to the discipline involved—medicine or biology, evolutionary biology or earth science? Focusing on either this threefold distinction or the disciplinary boundaries reveals that they might not be sufficient from a philosophical perspective. On the contrary, focusing on the interaction between these various kinds of models, some interesting forms of explanation come to the fore, as is exemplified by the papers included in this issue. On the other hand, a focus on the use of models, rather than on their content, shows that the distinction between biological and medical models is theoretically sound.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Belzung, C., & Lemoine, M. (2011). Criteria of validity for animal models of psychiatric disorders: focus on anxiety disorders and depression. Biology of Mood and Anxiety Disorders, 1(1), 1–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernard, C. (1865). Introduction à l’étude de la médecine expérimentale. Paris: Baillière.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brody, F., & Vamos, T. (Eds.). (1995). The neumann compendium. Boston: World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burian, R. (1993). How the choice of experimental organism matters: epistemological reflections on an aspect of biological practice. Journal of the History of Biology, 26(2), 351–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Ménuret Chambaud, J. J. (1765). Observateur. In D. Diderot & J. d’Alembert (Eds.), Encyclopédie (Vol. 11, pp. 310–313). Paris: Briasson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2010). Models and fiction. Synthese, 172(2), 251–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J. (2006). Les organismes modèles en biologie et en médecine. In G. Gachelin (Ed.), Les organismes modèles dans la recherché médicale (pp. 9–43). Paris: PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (2006). Scientific perspectivism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, K. (1939). The organism: A holistic approach to biology derived from pathological data in man, New York: American Book Company (Translation of Aufbau des Organismus. Einführung in die Biologie unter besonderer Berücksichtigung der Erfahrungen am kranken Menschen), Den Haag: Nijhoff, 1934.

  • Grune-Yanoff, T., & Weirich, P. (2010). Philosophy of simulation. Simulation and Gaming, 41(1), 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • LaFollette, H., & Shanks, N. (1995). Two models of models in biomedical research. The Philosophical Quarterly, 45(179), 141–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli, S., & Ankeny, R. (2012). Re-thinking organisms: The epistemic impact of databases on model organism biology. Studies in the History and Philosophy of the Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43, 29–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levins, R. (1966). The strategy of model building in population biology. American Scientist, 54, 421–431.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthewson, J., & Weisberg, M. (2009). The structure of trade-offs in model building. Synthese, 170(1), 169–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maugeri, P., & Blasimme, A. (2011). Humanised models of cancer in molecular medicine: the experimental control of disanalogy. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 33(1), 603–622.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard-Smith, J. (1982). Evolution and the theory of games. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. (2003). Biological complexity and integrative pluralism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M., & Morrison, M. (Eds.). (1999). Models as mediators. Perspectives on natural and social science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (2000). Unifying scientific theories. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N. (2008). Creating scientific concepts. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley, M., & Soyer, O. (2011). The roles of integration in molecular systems biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43, 58–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffner, K. (1993). Discovery and explanation in biology and medicine. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steel, D. (2008). Across the boundaries: Extrapolation in biology and social science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2009). Depth. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppe, F. (1989). The semantic view of theories and scientific realism. Chicago: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1960). A comparison of the meaning and uses of models in mathematics and the empirical sciences. Synthese, 12, 287–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (2005). Philosophy of experimental biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. (1987). False Models as Means to Truer Theories. In N. Nitecki & A. Hoffman (Eds.), Neutral models in biology (pp. 23–55). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, E. (2010). Science in the age of computer simulation. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Philippe Huneman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Huneman, P., Lemoine, M. Introduction: the plurality of modeling. HPLS 36, 5–15 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-014-0002-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-014-0002-5

Keywords

Navigation