Skip to main content
Log in

Addressing Deficits and Injustices: The Potential Epistemic Contributions of Patients to Research

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Health Care Analysis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Patient or public involvement (PPI) in health research is increasingly expected as a matter of policy. In theory, PPI can contribute both to the epistemic aims intrinsic to research (generating knowledge), and to extrinsically valued features of research such as social inclusion and transparency. In practice, the aims of PPI have not always been clear, although there has been a tendency to encourage the involvement of so-called ordinary people who are regarded as representative of an assumed patient perspective. In this paper we focus on the epistemic potential of PPI, using theoretical work in epistemology to develop a nuanced account of patients’ experiential knowledge and how this might contribute directly to conceptual development, hypothesis generation and data interpretation. We also consider how some features of health research pose barriers to this kind of epistemic contribution. Drawing on Miranda Fricker’s idea of testimonial injustice, we explore how disciplinary indicators of credibility in clinical and academic health research contexts might be wrongly applied to those involved in PPI, undermining their potential to contribute. Finally we argue for a range of strategies to maximize opportunities for patients to engage with research teams and make epistemologically significant contributions to research.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Systematic reviews of PPI show little or inconclusive evidence of the impact of PPI [3, 5, 6, 12, 43].

  2. Elsewhere in the literature [50] authors distinguish ethical, political, and methodological aims. Of these, the first two fit into our ‘extrinsic’ category, whereas the third fits our ‘intrinsic’ category. Similar distinctions have been made by others, e.g. [9]. p. 2576; [49]. p. 2. It is worth noting that some benefits fall into a grey area. For example, involvement of patients in research design with the aim of improving the experience of the research participants by ensuring that their experience is pleasant, not inadvertently undermining of dignity, not too difficult etc. obviously has extrinsic value (i.e. ethical value of improving the experience of participants) but might also impact on comprehensiveness of data collection by increasing the number of respondents or completers, or improving the accuracy or richness of what they say. Conversely, there are moral reasons for promoting the epistemic benefits of PPI (for example doing so will lead to better utilization of health resources) and, as we will discuss, moral or ethical issues can arise in relation to the pursuit of PPI for epistemic aims.

  3. Examples of such indirect benefits are reported in [24].

  4. We recognize concerns expressed elsewhere that the term ‘patient’ can suggest sickness, passivity and disempowerment [5], although the term is claimed by some patient activists. We prefer ‘patient’ to ‘consumer’, which seems to refer more broadly to someone who is or might be a user of various health-related services, and is also suggestive of a particular kind of (economic) relationship (a point made by Angus Dawson [14]).

  5. Groups with other perspectives (such as carers or clinicians) might also have unique forms of knowledge that could enhance the conceptualization, design and conduct of health research. Such questions lie beyond the scope of this paper, but some of our arguments, relevantly modified, might apply to other groups.

  6. This terminology is courtesy of Donald Rumsfeld, who said: “There are known knowns. These are things we know that we know. There are known unknowns. That is to say, there are things that we know we don't know. But there are also unknown unknowns. There are things we don't know we don't know.” As David Logan observes [27], Rumsfeld’s comments gesture towards an idea that is useful in the context of scientific knowledge.

  7. Although we note that there is ongoing controversy over whether or not GWS is caused by an unknown medical problem (for example related to immune function) or whether it is psychogenic [22].

  8. Gronseth [22] reports that some veterans wore pet flea collars to repel insects.

  9. Chalmers does not reference this claim, therefore we are unable to provide further details.

  10. For example, one biomedical scientist said: “Patients should not interfere in processes of which they know nothing about.” [9 p. 2576].

  11. For example, Thompson et al. quote a patient involved as a research collaborator as saying: “You need to put brain into gear before opening mouth. You can’t just sit and waffle… [health researchers don’t] suffer fools gladly” [47 p. 613].

  12. The Project LEAD® institute also provides intensive science course for breast cancer advocates in the USA [42].

  13. Some forms of indirect epistemic contribution may benefit from those involved in a PPI capacity lacking technical knowledge or skills, for example the ability to identify that ordinary patients will not understand an information sheet due to jargon, or sensitivity to how those with limited understanding of research will react to various recruitment protocols.

  14. The website of Harvard’s “Project Implicit” includes such resources for combating implicit bias generally, although the details are not specific to implicit biases in the health research context [36].

  15. The possibility of using focus groups suggests a related but less direct way that patients’ first-hand knowledge of their health conditions might lead to epistemic breakthroughs. That is, when researchers make detailed use of qualitative studies of patient experiences. Careful analysis of already articulated patient experiential knowledge might stimulate new ideas when considered by researchers in light of their existing knowledge and research questions. Although not strictly a case of patient involvement, this is worth noting here because it seems a natural extension of our account of the role of experiential knowledge in achieving the epistemic goals of health research. Further examination of the potential of forms of qualitative research such as in-depth interviews and focus groups seems warranted. This point reinforces earlier recommendations along these lines [18].

References

  1. Australian Government National Health and Medical Research Council NHMRC. (2015). A12. Consumer and community participation in health and medical research. https://www.nhmrc.gov.au/book/nhmrc-funding-rules/section-nhmrc-funding-rules/a12-consumer-and-community-participation-health. Accessed November 2015.

  2. Australian Government National Health and Medical Research Council NHMRC and Consumers’ Health Forum of Australia. (2005). A model framework for consumer and community participation in health and medical research. Canberra. https://www.nhmrc.gov.au/_files_nhmrc/publications/attachments/r33.pdf. Accessed November 2015.

  3. Barber, R., Boote, J. D., Parry, G. D., Cooper, C. L., Yeeles, P., & Cook, S. (2012). Can the impact of public involvement on research be evaluated? A mixed methods study. Health Expectations, 15(3), 229–241.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  4. Boghossian, P. A. (1989). Content and self-knowledge. Philosophical Topics, 17(1), 5–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Boote, J., Telford, R., & Cooper, C. (2002). Consumer involvement in health research: A review and research agenda. Health Policy, 61(2), 213–236.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  6. Brett, J., Staniszewska, S., Mockford, C., Herron-Marx, S., Hughes, J., Tysall, C., & Suleman, R. (2014). Mapping the impact of patient and public involvement on health and social care research: A systematic review. Health Expectations, 17(5), 637–650.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  7. Brouwers, M., Kho, M. E., Browman, G. P., Cluzeau, F., Feder, G., Fervers, B., et al. (2010). Next steps consortium. AGREE II: Advancing guideline development, reporting and evaluation in healthcare. Canadian Medical Association Journal, 182(18), E839–E842.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  8. Caress, A. L., Ford, A., Roberts, L., Turner, K., Ward, D., & Williamson, T. (2012). Briefing notes for researchers: Public involvement in NHS, public health and social care research. INVOLVE. http://www.invo.org.uk/wpcontent/uploads/2014/11/9938_INVOLVE_Briefing_Notes_WEB.pdf. Accessed November 2015.

  9. Caron-Flinterman, J. F., Broerse, J. E., & Bunders, J. F. (2005). The experiential knowledge of patients: A new resource for biomedical research? Social Science and Medicine, 60(11), 2575–2584.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  10. Chalmers, I. (1995). What do I want from health research and researchers when I am a patient? British Medical Journal, 310(6990), 1315.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  11. Church, J., Saunders, D., Wanke, M., Pong, R., Spooner, C., & Dorgan, M. (2002). Citizen participation in health decision-making: Past experience and future prospects. Journal of Public Health Policy, 23(1), 12–32.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  12. Conklin, A., Morris, Z., & Nolte, E. (2015). What is the evidence base for public involvement in health-care policy? Results of a systematic scoping review. Health Expectations, 18(2), 153–165.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  13. Davies, G., & Burgess, J. (2004). Challenging the ‘view from nowhere’: Citizen reflections on specialist expertise in a deliberative process. Health and Place, 10(4), 349–361.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  14. Dawson, A. (2010). The future of bioethics: Three dogmas and a cup of hemlock. Bioethics, 24(5), 218–225.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  15. Department of Health. (2005). Research Governance Framework for Health and Social Care. p. 20. https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/139565/dh_4122427.pdf. Accessed November 2015.

  16. Emmerova, M., & Jirava, F. (2004). Is gulf war syndrome really a mystery? Medicine, Conflict and Survival, 20(3), 209–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Entwistle, V. A. (2009). Public involvement in health service governance and development: Questions of potential for influence. Health Expectations, 12(1), 1–3.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  18. Entwistle, V. A., Renfrew, M. J., Yearley, S., Forrester, J., & Lamont, T. (1998). Lay perspectives: Advantages for health research. British Medical Journal, 316(7129), 463–466.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  19. Entwistle, V. A., McCaughan, D., Watt, I. S., Birks, Y., Hall, J., Peat, M., et al. (2010). Speaking up about safety concerns: Multi-setting qualitative study of patients’ views and experiences. Quality and Safety in Health Care, 19(6), e33.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  20. Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  21. Gersons, B. P., & Carlier, I. V. (1992). Post-traumatic stress disorder: The history of a recent concept. The British Journal of Psychiatry, 161(6), 742–748.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  22. Gronseth, G. S. (2005). Gulf war syndrome: A toxic exposure? A systematic review. Neurologic Clinics, 23(2), 523–540.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  23. Knowles, S., Planner, C., Donnelly, A., & Bourke, S. Hacking into health research. BMJ Blog. http://blogs.bmj.com/bmj/2014/10/29/sarah-knowles-etal-hacking-into-health-research/. Accessed November 2015.

  24. Langston, A. L., McCallum, M., Campbell, M. K., Robertson, C., & Ralston, S. H. (2005). An integrated approach to consumer representation and involvement in a multicentre randomized controlled trial. Clinical Trials, 2(1), 80–87.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  25. Levit, M. (1953). On the psychology and philosophy of concept formation. Educational Theory, 3(3), 193–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Lockey, R., Sitzia, J., Gillingham, T., Millyard, J., Miller, C., Ahmed, S., et al. (2004). Training for service user involvement in health and social care research: A study of training provision and participants’ experiences (The TRUE Project). Worthing: Worthing and Southlands Hospitals NHS Trust.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Logan, D. C. (2009). Known knowns, known unknowns, unknown unknowns and the propagation of scientific enquiry. Journal of Experimental Botany, 60(3), 712–714.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  28. Lupton, Deborah. (2003). Medicine as culture: Illness, disease and the body in western societies (2nd ed.). Beverly Hills: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Malterud, K. (1999). The (gendered) construction of diagnosis interpretation of medical signs in women patients. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 20(3), 275–286.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  30. Myers, C. S. (1916). Contributions to the study of shell shock. Being an account of certain disorders of speech, with special reference to their causation and their relation to malingering. The Lancet, 188(4854), 461–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, 84(3), 231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. O’Donnell, M., & Entwistle, V. (2004). Consumer involvement in research projects: The activities of research funders. Health Policy, 69(2), 229–238.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  33. O’Donnell, M., & Entwistle, V. (2004). Consumer involvement in decisions about what health related research is funded. Health Policy, 70(3), 281–290.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  34. Patient-Centered Outcomes Research Institute PCORI. (2015). What we mean by engagement. Washington, DC. http://www.pcori.org/funding-opportunities/what-we-mean-engagement. Accessed November 2015.

  35. Prior, L. (2003). Belief, knowledge and expertise: The emergence of the lay expert in medical sociology. Sociology of Health and Illness, 25(3), 41–57.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  36. Project Implicit. https://implicit.harvard.edu/implicit/demo/background/index.jsp. Accessed November 2015.

  37. Russell, B. (1912). Knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description. In The problems of philosophy (Chap. 5, pp. 25–32). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  38. Schwitzgebel, E. (2002). How well do we know our own conscious experience? The case of visual imagery. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 9(5–6), 35–53.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Schwitzgebel, E. (2008). The unreliability of naive introspection. Philosophical Review, 117(2), 245–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1(19), 253–329.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Spence, D. L. (2007). Ensuring respect for persons when recruiting junior enlisted personnel for research. Military Medicine, 172(3), 250–253.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  42. Srivastava, R. (2013). Speaking up—When doctors navigate medical hierarchy. New England Journal of Medicine, 368(4), 302–305.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  43. Staley, K., Buckland, S. A., Hayes, H., & Tarpey, M. (2014). ‘The missing links’: Understanding how context and mechanism influence the impact of public involvement in research. Health Expectations, 17(6), 755–764.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  44. Subramaniam, M., Perrucci, R., & Whitlock, D. (2014). Intellectual closure: A theoretical framework linking knowledge, power, and the corporate university. Critical Sociology, 40(3), 411–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Tarn, M., Greenberg, N., & Wessely, S. (2008). Gulf War syndrome—has it gone away? Advances in Psychiatric Treatment, 14(6), 414–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. Terry, S. F., Terry, P. F., Rauen, K. A., Uitto, J., & Bercovitch, L. G. (2007). Advocacy groups as research organisations: The PXE international example. Nature Reviews Genetics, 8(2), 157–164.41.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  47. Thompson, J., Bissell, P., Cooper, C., Armitage, C. J., & Barber, R. (2012). Credibility and the ‘professionalized’ lay expert: Reflections on the dilemmas and opportunities of public involvement in health research. Health, 16(6), 602–618.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  48. Trimble, M. R. (1985). Post-traumatic stress disorder: History of a concept. In C. R. Figley (Ed.), Trauma and its wake (Vol. 1, pp. 5–14). New York: Brunner/Mazel.

    Google Scholar 

  49. van de Bovenkamp, H. M., & Zuiderent-Jerak, T. (2015). An empirical study of patient participation in guideline development: Exploring the potential for articulating patient knowledge in evidence-based epistemic settings. Health Expectations, 18(5), 942–955.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  50. Ward, P. R., Thompson, J., Barber, R., Armitage, C. J., Boote, J. D., Cooper, C. L., & Jones, G. L. (2010). Critical perspectives on ‘consumer involvement’ in health research: Epistemological dissonance and the know-do gap. Journal of Sociology, 46(1), 63–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Wiltshire, H. (1916). A contribution to the etiology of shell shock. The Lancet, 187(4842), 1207–1212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Zelek, B., & Phillips, S. P. (2003). Gender and power: Nurses and doctors in Canada. International Journal for Equity in Health, 2(1), 1.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  53. Ziebland, S., & Wyke, S. (2012). Health and illness in a connected world: How might sharing experiences on the internet affect people’s health? Milbank Quarterly, 90(2), 219–249.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The research for this paper was primarily funded by an Australian Research Council (ARC) grant (DP120101092), How do we know what works? Ethics and evidence in surgical research. Katrina Hutchison’s research was also partly funded by the ARC Centre of Excellence for Electromaterials Science, where she has worked since June 2015. Discussions about the paper were facilitated by Macquarie University funding of a visit by Vikki A. Entwistle to participate in a Centre for Agency, Values and Ethics (CAVE) seminar on Capabilities Approaches to Justice. The authors would like to thank the anonymous reviewers for a number of helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Katrina Hutchison.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hutchison, K., Rogers, W. & Entwistle, V.A. Addressing Deficits and Injustices: The Potential Epistemic Contributions of Patients to Research. Health Care Anal 25, 386–403 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-016-0323-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10728-016-0323-5

Keywords

Navigation