Skip to main content
Log in

Varieties of Sobel sequences

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Linguistics and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I provide a unified analysis of a number of pragmatic anomalies that have been discussed in the literature. The paper’s main goal is to account for Sobel sequences of conditionals and sequences of disjunctive sentences, but I will also propose that this analysis can be extended to sequences of sentences with superlatives. The starting point is the observation that, while all these sequences are felicitous in one order, they are infelicitous when the order is reversed. Previous proposals have focussed on particular types of infelicitous sequences (e.g. von Fintel, in: Kenstowicz (ed) Ken Hale: A life in language, MIT Press, Cambridge, 2001; Moss in Noûs 46:516–586, 2012; Lewis in Noûs 52:481–507, 2018; a.o.), or a subset of all the phenomena cited above (e.g. Singh in On competition between only and exh, 2008b; Linguist Philos 31:245–260, 2008c; Dohrn, in: Pistoia-Reda, Domaneschi (eds) Linguistic and psycholinguistic approaches on implicatures and presuppositions. Palgrave McMillan, Basingstoke, 2017; a.o.). I propose that sequences of sentences belonging to the same structured set of alternatives T are subject to a Specificity Constraint (SC): sequences are acceptable if both alternatives are dominated by the same number of nodes in the structured set of alternatives T. Violations of SC can be avoided by strengthening the weaker alternative. However, covert strengthening violates an economy condition if the overtly stronger alternative is among those made salient by the preceding utterance in the sequence (if any). I propose that the set of alternatives made salient by an utterance of a sentence s consists of s’s sisters and mother in T. I will show that the strengthening mechanism varies depending on the kind of sequence we have.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Alonso-Ovalle, L. (2006). Disjunction in alternative semantics. Ph.D. thesis, UMass, Amherst.

  • Büring, D. (2003). On D-trees, beans, and B-accents. Linguistics and Philosophy, 26, 511–545.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G., Fox, D., & Spector, B. (2012). The grammatical view of scalar implicatures and the relationship between semantics and pragmatics. In C. Maienborn, K. von Heusinger, & P. Portner (Eds.), Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning (Vol. 3, pp. 2297–2332). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dohrn, D. (2017). Presuppositional anaphora is the sobel truth. In S. Pistoia-Reda & F. Domaneschi (Eds.), Linguistic and psycholinguistic approaches on implicatures and presuppositions (pp. 199–238). Basingstoke: Palgrave McMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edgington, D. (1995). On conditionals. Mind, 104, 235–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, D. (2005). Economy and scope. Natural Language Semantics, 3, 283–341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, D., & Katzir, R. (2011). On the characterization of alternatives. Natural Language Semantics, 19, 87–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazdar, G. (1979). Pragmatics: Implicatures, presuppositions and logical form. Cambridge: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geurts, B. (2005). Entertaining alternatives: Disjunctions as modals. Natural Language Semantics, 13, 383–410.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, A. (2012). Indicative conditionals. In G. Russell & D. G. Fara (Eds.), Routledge companion to the philosophy of language (pp. 449–465). Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, T. (2007). Counterfactual Scorekeeping. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30, 329–360.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, J. (1999). The logic of interrogation. In T. Matthews & D. L. Strolovitch (Eds.), Proceedings of SALT IX (pp. 109–126). Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. (1990). Presupposition projection. In R. van der Sandt (Ed.), Presupposition, lexical meaning and discourse processes: Workshop reader.

  • Heim, I. (1991). Articles and definiteness. In A. von Stechow & D. Wunderlich (Eds.), Semantics. An international handbook of contemporary research (pp. 487–535). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. (1992). Presupposition projection and the semantics of attitude verbs. Journal of Semantics, 9, 183–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. (1995). Notes on superlatives. Manuscript, MIT.

  • Holst, M. A. (2012). Incomplete descriptions and (reverse) Sobel sequences. Analysis, 1, 26–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. (1969). A presuppositional analysis of ‘only’ and ‘even’. In R. I. Binnick, A. Davison, G. Green, & J. Morgan (Eds.), Papers from the fifth regional meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society (pp. 98–107). Chicago, IL: Chicago Linguistic Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. (1996). Exclusive company: ‘Only’ and the dynamics of vertical inference. Journal of Semantics, 13, 1–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. (1997). All John’s children are as bald as the king of France: Existential import and the geometry of opposition. In K. Singer, R. Eggert, & G. Anderson (Eds.), Papers form the 33rd regional meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society (pp. 155–179). Chigaco, IL: Chicago Linguistic Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. (2018). Ceteris paribusiness: On the power of salient exceptions. Manuscript.

  • Hurford, J. (1974). Exclusive or inclusive disjunction. Foundations of Language, 11, 409–411.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ippolito, M. (2007). On the meaning of some focus-sensitive particles. Natural Language Semantics, 15(1), 1–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ippolito, M. (2016). How similar is similar enough? Semantics and Pragmatics, 9, 1–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katzir, R. (2007). Structurally-defined alternatives. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30, 669–690.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katzir, R., & Singh, R. (2014). Hurford disjunctions: Embedded exhaustification and structural economy. In U. Etxeberria, A. Fălăuş, A. Irurtzun, & L. Bryan (Eds.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 18 (pp. 201–216).

  • Klecha, P. (2014). Two kinds of sobel sequences: Precision in conditionals. In U. Steindl, T. Borer, H. Fang, A. García Pardo, P. Guekguezian, B. Hsu, C. O’Hara, & I. Chuoying Ouyang (Eds.), Proceedings of WCCFL (Vol. 32, pp. 131–140). Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. (1989). An investigation of the lumps of thought. Linguistics and Philosophy, 12, 607–653.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriz̆, M. (2015). Homogeneity, non-maximality, and all. Journal of Semantics, 33, 493–539.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, R., Bergen, L., & Goodman, N. (2014). Roses and flowers: An informativeness implicature in probabilistic pragmatics. Slides from Semantics and Linguistic Theory 24 held at NYU, May 30 2014.

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Counterfactual dependence and time’s arrow. Noûs, 13, 455–476.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, K. (2018). Counterfactual discourse in context. Noûs, 52, 481–507.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magri, G. (2009). A theory of individual-level predicates based on blind mandatory scalar implicatures. Natural Language Semantics, 17, 245–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moss, S. (2012). On the pragmatics of counterfactuals. Noûs, 46, 516–586.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nolan, D. (2003). Defending a possible-worlds account of indicative conditionals. Philosophical Studies, 116, 215–269.

    Google Scholar 

  • Percus, O. (2006). Antipresuppositions. In A. Ueyama (Ed.), Theoretical and empirical studies of reference and anaphora: Toward the establishment of generative grammar as an empirical science. Report of the grant-in-aid for scientific research (B), project no. 15320052, Japan Society for the Promotion of Science, pp. 52–73.

  • Potts, C. (2008). Wait a minute! What kind of discourse strategy is this?. Manuscript.

  • Roberts, C. (2012/1996). Information structure in discourse: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. Semantics and Pragmatics, 5. https://doi.org/10.3765/sp.5.6. First published in Y. Jae-Hak & A. Kathol (Eds.), Papers in semantics (Working Papers in Linguistics 49). The Ohio State University, 1996

  • Rooth, M. (1992). A theory of focus interpretation. Natural Language Semantics, 1, 75–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rooth, M. (1996). Focus. In S. Lappin (Ed.), The handbook of contemporary semantic theory (pp. 271–297). Hoboken: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, M. (2005). Dividing things up: The semantics of or and the modal/or interaction. Natural Language Semantics, 13, 271–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, M. (2011). Dynamic pragmatics, or why we shouldn’t be afraid of embedded implicatures. In N. Ashton, A. Chereches, & D. Lutz (Eds.), Proceedings of SALT XXI (pp. 609–633). Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singh, R. (2008a). Modularity and locality in interpretation. Ph.D. thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

  • Singh, R. (2008b). On competition between only and exh. Handout, MIT June 6, 2008.

  • Singh, R. (2008c). On the interpretation of disjunction: Asymmetric, incremental, and eager for inconsistency. Linguistics and Philosophy, 31, 245–260.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1975). Indicative conditionals. Philosophia, 5, 269–286.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2002). Nominal restriction. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Logical form and language (pp. 365–388). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szabolcsi, A. (2002). Hungarian disjunctions and positive polarity. In I. Kenesei & P. Siptár (Eds.), Approaches to Hungarian (Vol. 8, pp. 217–241). Budapest: Akadémiai Kiadó.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tichy, P. (1976). A counterexample to the Stalnaker–Lewis analysis of counterfactuals. Philosophical Studies, 29, 271–273.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Rooij, R. & Schulz, K. (2005). Only: Meaning and implicatures. Manuscript.

  • Veltman, F. (2005). Making counterfactual assumptions. Journal of Semantics, 22, 159–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K. (2001). Counterfactuals in a dynamic context. In M. Kenstowicz (Ed.), Ken Hale: A life in language (pp. 123–152). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K. (2004). Would you believe it? The king of France is back! Presuppositions and truth-value intuitions. In M. Reimer & A. Bezuidenhout (Eds.), Descriptions and beyond (pp. 315–341). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K., & Gillies, A. (2013). \(> ={}_\square {}\). MIT and Rutgers University.

  • Willer, M. (2017). Lessons from Sobel sequences. Semantics and Pragmatics, 10(4), 1–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmermann, E. (2000). Free choice disjunction and epistemic possibility. Natural Language Semantics, 8, 255–290.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

The funding was provided by Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (Grant No. 496697).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michela Ippolito.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

I would like to thank the editors and two anonymous reviewers for Linguistics and Philosophy for their extensive and helpful comments on an earlier draft. This work benefitted from discussions with the audiences at Philosophical Linguistics and Linguistical Philosophy 4 conference (2017), the Vendler Research Group in Linguistics and Philosophy at the University of Calgary (2018), and the Topics at the Semantics-Pragmatics Interface workshop at UCSC (2018). This work has been supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council, Insight Grant #496697.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ippolito, M. Varieties of Sobel sequences. Linguist and Philos 43, 633–671 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-019-09281-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-019-09281-8

Keywords

Navigation