Skip to main content
Log in

Are knowledge ascriptions sensitive to social context?

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Plausibly, how much is at stake in some salient practical task can affect how generously people ascribe knowledge of task-relevant facts. There is a metaphysical puzzle about this phenomenon, and an empirical puzzle. Metaphysically: there are competing theories about when and how practical stakes affect whether it is correct to ascribe knowledge. Which of these theories is the right one? Empirically: experimental philosophy has struggled to find a stakes-effect on people’s knowledge ascriptions. Is the alleged phenomenon just a philosopher’s fantasy?

I propose a new psychological account of when and why people’s knowledge ascriptions are sensitive to stakes. My hypothesis is motivated by empirical research on how people’s judgements are sensitive to their social context. Specifically, people’s evaluations are sensitive to their ‘psychological distance’ from the scenarios they are considering. When using ‘fixed-evidence probes’, experimental philosophy has found that what’s at stake for a fictional character in a made-up scenario has little or no effect on how participants ascribe knowledge to them. My hypothesis predicts this finding: the scenarios are too ‘psychologically distant’ to participants. Our empirical puzzle is resolved: the stakes-effect often present in the wild won’t be present in vignette studies. (This illustrates a widespread problem with X-phi vignette studies: if people might judge differently in other social contexts, we can’t generalize from the results of these experiments. That is, vignette studies are of doubtful ‘external validity’.) The hypothesis also resolves our metaphysical puzzle. It predicts that people do not ascribe knowledge in a way deemed correct by any of the standard philosophical views, namely classical invariantism, interest-relative invariantism, and contextualism. Our knowledge ascriptions shift around in the way that’s most useful for social beings like us, and this pattern in our judgements can only be endorsed by a genuinely relativist metaphysics for knowledge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. DeRose (1992; 2009: 1–9) and Stanley (2005: 3–5) give cases like this; Cohen’s (1999) ‘airport’ case is similar. The example should not also vary which possibilities of error are salient.

  2. Interest-relative invariantism is defended by Hawthorne (2004 chapter 4—tentatively), Stanley (2005), Fantl and McGrath (2009, 2012), and Weatherson (2012).

  3. Contextualists include DeRose (1992, 2009), Cohen (1999), Lewis (1996), Greco (2008: 432–5), Fricker (2008), Henderson (2011), Hannon (2013), McKenna (2013), and Blome-Tillmann (2014). ‘WAM-ing invariantism’ is the view that while “knows” always semantically expresses the same thing, people use the word to conversationally implicate a variety of other epistemic states, with results similar to contextualism; see §6.

  4. Classical invariantism is defended by Williamson (2005), Nagel (2010), Gerken (2017 chapter 12), and Dinges (2019 chapter 8).

  5. Philosophers endorsing this notion of outright judgement include Harman (1986, chapters 3 & 5), Nagel (2010), Weisberg (2016), Holton (2014), Staffel (2013, 2019) and Friedman (2019). Occurrent partial belief is very different from ‘credence’, a dispositional notion defined in terms of betting behavior employed by decision theorists and formal epistemologists (Easwaran, 2011a, 2011b). Nor should occurrent partial belief be tied to the ‘epistemic’ or ‘evidential’ probabilities postulated by some philosophers (Williamson, 2000: chapters 9 & 10; Fantl & McGrath, 2009: chapters 1 & 7).

  6. One might object that ‘perceptual choices’ are not outright judgements, but plans to press one button or the other. But one can judge that the dots are mostly moving to the left; and one can act on the basis of such a judgement, say by pressing a button. That’s how you’d approach a one-off instance of the task without time-pressure or reward. We’d need good reason to think things are different when people participate in studies concerning perceptual choice.

  7. Standage et al. (2014 §4) argue that stakes also affect how evidence is encoded, and how it is then integrated.

  8. DeRose (2009: 270–3) raises a case in which the subject acts on two practical questions separately but at once, using incompatible attitudes. Jane’s employer offers her a year’s free life insurance. She walks over to the benefits office to sign up—after all, you never know what might happen. On the way, Jane answers her cell phone. It’s one of Jane’s friends, asking whether she’s going to look for a different job in the near future. Jane says she won’t—she’ll still be working at the same place this time next year. She carries on walking to the benefits office for life insurance while occurrently judging that next year she will still be working at the same place, and thus assuming she won’t die in the meantime. She is able to keep separate the two settings in which the question arises as to where she’ll be in a year’s time. If Jane is asked why she is walking to the benefits office, she’ll revert to suspending judgement on whether she’ll be alive and working there this time next year. Jane is able to switch back and forth between calibrating to one practical task or the other, and thus the appropriate attitude to whether she’ll be working in the same place next year. This psychological ability is crucial to computationally efficient reasoning.

  9. Other arguments that cognition is sensitive to the social context include: Smith & Semin (2004), Schwartz (2007), and Yeh & Barsalou (2006).

  10. Nagel (2010: 408) cites that ‘knows’ is one of the ten most common verbs in English. Knowledge ascriptions dwarf evaluations of epistemic rationality or justification, even if only half of uses of “knows” are epistemic evaluations (Hansen et al., 2019: 12).

  11. Shea et al. (2014) argue that the function of communicable metacognitive representations—presumably including knowledge ascriptions—is to improve complex cooperation. The suggestion is compatible with the concept of knowledge having evolved culturally rather than genetically (Shea et al., 2014: 191, Heyes 2018 chapter 7).

  12. Nagel (2012: 186) anticipates claim (2). She suggests that “our own way of thinking” provides the “standard for evaluating the subject’s thinking”. There’s precedent for the idea that the mechanisms regulating one’s beliefs are central to evaluating the beliefs of others. Plausibly, the mechanisms regulating how we act play a role in evaluating the actions of others. According to Miller & Cushman (2013), we sometimes evaluate others morally by simulating acting in the relevant ways ourselves, and seeing how that would make us feel.

  13. Turri et al. (2016) argue empirically that judgements about what someone should do (‘actionability judgements’) have a strong causal impact on our ascriptions of knowledge to them. According to (2), actionability judgements and knowledge ascriptions are instead sensitive to a common cause, namely one’s implicit standard for full belief, which is sensitive to the demands of the task one calibrates to. Turri et al. admit that their results can be well accounted for by such a common cause (2016: 220). They measure assertibility judgements rather than actionability judgements generally, which might be a special case (§8).

  14. Nagel (2012) repudiates her (2010) psychological hypothesis, but still seems to be assuming classical invariantism. Considering possibilities of error makes us deny that more innocent subjects have knowledge. For example: if we consider the counterfactual possibility that the clock had stopped, then we judge that Wanda’s glance at the clock is not enough for her to know that it is 4:15 pm (Nagel 2012: 174–5). Nagel claims that we must reject these intuitions on the pain of general skepticism (p. 187). But that’s not right according to contextualism, nor the bolder relativism I favour (§9).

  15. Nagel (2010) and Gerken (2017 chapter 12) argue that their hypotheses are well-motivated by existing psychological theories, but that’s been challenged vigorously. Dimmock (2019) criticises Nagel’s appeal to ‘egocentric bias’, and Dinges (2019: 121–5) criticises Gerken’s appeal to ‘attribute substitution’.

    Nagel’s (2010) proposal is not designed to explain the X-phi results, and the prospects strike me as dim. Because it appeals to ‘egocentric bias’, Nagel’s theory implies that people with higher ‘need for cognition’ will show weaker stakes effects (Alexander et al., 2014). Philosophers have higher need for cognition than most people. So Nagel’s theory predicts that philosophers will show weaker stakes effects than ordinary people. That’s backwards: X-phi finds that ordinary people have stakes insensitive responses to vignettes, while many philosophers report stakes sensitive intuitions (§§7–8). It would be good to solidify this argument by testing whether need for cognition correlates with an individual’s stakes sensitivity, like Alexander et al. do for sensitivity to salient possibilities of error. Nagel (2012: 182–8) gives other reasons to doubt her (2010) hypothesis.

  16. Could IRI weasel out of this indictment, claiming that talking to Hannah puts Bill in a high-stakes situation without him realizing? Then Bill doesn’t know, as per Hannah’s useful evaluation. (Stanley, 2005: 118–9 considers this manoeuvre.) This weaselling doesn’t solve the problem. Suppose that not much is at stake for Amy, and Bill tells her that the bank will be open on Saturday morning—he was there on a Saturday a couple of months back. Hannah eavesdrops. Hannah should still think Bill doesn’t know. But surely Hannah’s interests don’t trump Amy’s in defining Bill’s practical situation. The deep problem here for IRI is that people should be able to assess whether Bill knows using whatever standard is relevant to them. The next section brings this out by considering the useful knowledge ascriptions of both Hannah’s friends and Bill’s friends.

  17. Even if CLT is not the right account of stakes effects, it may be the right account of other effects on information search and knowledge ascriptions. For example, Halamish and Liberman (2017) find that people underweight how annoying it is to sample marbles from two urns 100 times, when imaging doing it in a year’s time, or someone else doing it. Halamish & Liberman give a CLT explanation: when considering those psychologically distant scenarios, people represent the sampling process abstractly, rather than in concrete detail. That’s compatible with my proposal. However, they say CLT supports a general claim: “Psychological distance from a decision situation makes people construct larger data bases from which to draw conclusions.” (2017: 111.) If there is such a tendency, it must typically be swamped: surely people don’t expend more cognitive effort the less action-relevant a question is for them.

  18. Many philosophers are attracted to principles like RKP:

    (RKP) S can take p to be available as a reason for acting iff S knows that p.

    (See Hawthorne & Stanley, 2008; Jackson, 2012.) An anonymous reviewer worries that my hypothesis predicts that people will accept counter-examples to RKP. That is: people would regularly make judgements of the form, “S doesn’t know that p but S should still act on p”, and, “S knows that p, but S shouldn’t act on p”, which they don’t. My hypothesis has no such consequence. Verdicts about whether S can take p to be a reason shift in lock-step with verdicts about whether S knows that p. Both are evaluated using an epistemic standard set by the task the judge calibrates to. (Considering what someone ought to do may often cause us to calibrate to their task—see the end of §8.)

  19. I will assume that participants reading the high- and low-stakes versions of the vignettes attribute the same evidence to the characters. Nagel (2010: 429 n. 6, and p.c.) and Pinillos (2011 §4.3) challenge this assumption. They suggest that when participants read about a character in a high-stakes situation who nevertheless takes themselves to know, participants assume the character must have very strong evidence. If that’s right, then fixed-evidence vignette surveys would not show up any stakes-sensitivity in participants’ knowledge ascriptions.

  20. Traditionalists should not gloat, for a related challenge arises for philosophers who rely on their own intuitions. Why rely on the intuitions one has in the seminar room, if one would give different verdicts in other, more engaged practical and social contexts?

  21. Buckwalter & Schaffer (2015: 211–215) argue that Pinillos’ evidence-seeking study found a stakes effect on something, just not on knowledge. They asked participants high- and low-stakes variants of the following questions about knowing, guessing, or hoping:

    How many times do you think Peter has to proofread his paper before he [knows/guesses/hopes] that there are no typos? ____ times.

    They found the same patterns of response for “knows”, “guesses”, and “hopes”. Surely there is a common cause to the common pattern: people interpreted the three stimuli as asking the same question. Buckwalter & Schaffer say that participants answer how many times Peter has to proofread his paper, ignoring the subsequent words about knowing, hoping, or guessing. I say that in all three cases, participants answer the question about knowing. Participants will re-interpret the questions about hoping and guessing, because those questions are irrelevant and daft. First, what Peter hopes or guesses is of no import in the scenario. Second, Peter does not need to proofread his paper at all before he hopes or guesses it has no typos. The only sensible question in the vicinity is the one about knowing (or the equivalent one as to whether to act on the premise that there are no typos—see note 18). (Compare Dinges, 2019: 140–2.)

  22. De Smedt and De Cruz (2015) argue that philosophical thought experiments typically don’t transport philosophers to the degree that reading science fiction does: thought experiment rarely cause strong emotions (though see FeldmanHall et al., 2012). I’ve claimed that philosophers—unlike survey participants—are transported enough by certain thought experiments to have stakes-sensitive intuitions about them. These claims are compatible, because it is easier to calibrate to a stranger’s task than to care about them. People usually give stakes-sensitive advice to a stranger asking for directions, even without a strong emotional reaction to their predicament.

  23. Turri et al. (2016) use judgements about what someone should assert (e.g. write in their report) as their examples of judgements about what someone should do (‘actionability judgements’). I’ve given a functional reason to think assertibility judgements and actionability judgements have different effects on calibration, and thus on knowledge ascription.

  24. Jackson (2016: 972–3) argues that the point of contemporary truth-relativism is to ground claims about when assertions and retractions are ‘correct’ or ‘acceptable’ in such a sense. One example is MacFarlane (2014: 103–111 & chapter 8), who gives a truth-relativist account of knowledge ascriptions.

References

  • Alexander, J., Gonnerman, C., & Waterman, J. (2014). Salience and epistemic egocentrism: An empirical study. In J. Beebe (Ed.), Advances in experimental epistemology. Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Appel, M., & Richter, T. (2010). Transportation and need for affect in narrative persuasion: A mediated moderation model. Media Psychology, 13(2), 101–135

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balci, F., Simen, P., Niyogi, R., Saxe, A., Hughes, J. A., Holmes, P., & Cohen, J. D. (2011). Acquisition of decision making criteria: reward rate ultimately beats accuracy. Attention, Perception, & Psychophysics, 73(2), 640–657

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartlett, G. (2018). Occurrent states. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 48(1), 1–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin, D. J., Berger, J. O., Johannesson, M., et al. (2018). Redefine statistical significance. Nature Human Behavior, 2, 6–10

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blome-Tillmann, M. (2013). Knowledge and implicatures. Synthese, 190, 4293–4319

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blome-Tillmann, M. (2014). Knowledge and Presuppositions. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bogacz, R. (2007). Optimal decision-making theories: linking neurobiology with behaviour. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11(3), 118–125

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogacz, R., Usher, M., Zhang, J., & McClelland, J. L. (2007). Extending a biologically inspired model of choice: multi-alternatives, nonlinearity and value-based multidimensional choice. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 362, 1655–1670

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogacz, R., Hu, P., Holmes, P., & Cohen, J. D. (2010). Do humans produce the speed–accuracy trade-off that maximizes reward rate? The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 63(5), 863–891.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bostyn, D. H., Sevenhant, S., & Roets, A. (2018). Of mice, men, and trolleys: Hypothetical judgment versus real-life behavior in trolley-style moral dilemmas. Psychological Science, 29(7), 1084–1093

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. (2006). Contextualism and warranted assertibility manoeuvres. Philosophical Studies, 130, 407–435

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckwalter, W., & Schaffer, J. (2015). Knowledge, stakes, and mistakes. Noûs, 49(2), 201–234

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, C., & Mobbs, D. (2017). Differences in behavior and brain activity during hypothetical and real choices. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 21(1), 46–56

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chittka, L., Skorupski, P., & Raine, N. E. (2009). Speed–accuracy tradeoffs in animal decision making. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 24(7), 400–407

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (1999). Contextualism, skepticism, and the structure of reasons. Philosophical Perspectives, 13, 57–89

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig, E. (1990). Knowledge and the state of nature. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Smedt, J., & De Cruz, H. (2015). The epistemic value of speculative fiction. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 39, 58–77

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (1992). Contextualism and knowledge attributions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52(4), 913–929

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (2009). The case for contextualism: Knowledge, skepticism, and context (Vol. 1). Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dimmock, P. (2019). Knowledge, belief, and egocentric bias. Synthese, 196(8), 3409–3432

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dinges, A. (2019). Knowledge, stakes and error: A psychological account. Klostermann.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Easwaran, K. (2011a). Bayesianism I: Introduction and arguments in favor. Philosophy Compass, 6, 312–320

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Easwaran, K. (2011b). Bayesianism II: Applications and criticisms. Philosophy Compass, 6, 321–332

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J. St. B. T., & Stanovich, K. E. (2013). Dual-process theories of higher cognition: Advancing the debate. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8(3), 223–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fantl, J., & McGrath, M. (2012). Arguing for shifty epistemology. In J. Brown & M. Gerken (Eds.), Knowledge ascriptions. Oxford University Press.

  • Fantl, J., & McGrath, M. (2009). Knowledge in an uncertain world. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Faw, B. (2009). Conflicting intuitions may be based on differing abilities: Evidence from mental imaging research. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 16(4), 45–68

    Google Scholar 

  • FeldmanHall, O., Mobbs, D., Evans, D., Hiscox, L., Navrady, L., & Dalgleish, T. (2012). What we say and what we do: The relationship between real and hypothetical moral choices. Cognition, 123(3), 434–441

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, A., & Zarpentine, C. (2010). Do you know more when it matters less? Philosophical Psychology, 23(5), 683–706

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fiedler, K., Jung, J., Wänke, M., & Alexopoulos, T. (2012). On the relations between distinct aspects of psychological distance: An ecological basis of construal-level theory. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 48, 1014–1021

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fiske, S. T. (1992). Thinking is for doing: Portraits of social cognition from daguerreotype to laserphoto. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 63(6), 877–889

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Francis, K. B., Howard, C., Howard, I. S., Gummerum, M., Ganis, G., Anderson, G., & Terbeck, S. (2016). Virtual morality: Transitioning from moral judgment to moral action? PloS One, 11(10), e0164374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Francis, K., Beaman, P., & Hansen, N. (2019). Stakes, scales, and skepticism. Ergo, 6(16), 427–487.

  • Fricker, M. (2008). Scepticism and the genealogy of knowledge: Situating epistemology in time. Philosophical Papers, 37(1), 27–50

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2019). Inquiry and belief. Nous, 53, 296–315

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerken, M. (2017). On folk epistemology: How we think and talk about knowledge. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, D. T., & Wilson, T. D. (2007). Prospection: experiencing the future. Science, 317, 1351–1354

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glöckner, A., Hilbig, B. E., & Jekel, M. (2014). What is adaptive about adaptive decision making? A parallel constraint satisfaction account. Cognition, 133(3), 641–666.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gold, J. I., & Shadlen, M. N. (2007). The Neural Basis of Decision Making. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 30, 535–574

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2008). What’s wrong with contextualism? The Philosophical Quarterly, 58(232), 416–436

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, M. C., & Brock, T. C. (2000). The role of transportation in the persuasiveness of public narratives. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79(5), 701–721

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, M. C., & Donahue, J. K. (2009). Simulated worlds: Transportation into narratives. In K.D Markman, W.M.P Klein, & J.A. Suhr (Eds.), Handbook of imagination and mental simulation (pp. 241–254). Routledge.

  • Grice, H. P. (1989). Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halamish, V., & Liberman, N. (2017). How much information to sample before making a decision? It’s a matter of psychological distance. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 71, 111–116

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hannon, M. (2013). The practical origins of epistemic contextualism. Erkenntnis, 78(4), 899–919

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, N. (2020). “Nobody would really talk that way!”: The critical project in contemporary ordinary language philosophy. Synthese, 197, 2433–2464

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, N., Porter, J. D., & Francis, K. (2019). A corpus study of ‘know’: On the verification of philosophers' frequency claims about language. Episteme. Advance online publication.

  • Hare, B. (2017). Survival of the friendliest: Homo sapiens evolved via selection for prosociality. Annual Review of Psychology, 68, 155–186

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1986). Change in view. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J., & Stanley, J. (2008). Knowledge and action. Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 571–590

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heitz, R. (2014). The speed-accuracy tradeoff: History, physiology, methodology, and behavior. Frontiers in Neuroscience, 8, 150.

  • Henderson, D. (2011). Gate-Keeping Contextualism. Episteme, 8(1), 83–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henderson, D., & Greco, J. (Eds.). (2015). Epistemic evaluation: Purposeful epistemology. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. M. (2018). Cognitive gadgets. Cambridge: Belknap Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Holmes, E. A., & Mathews, A. (2010). Mental imagery in emotion and emotional disorders. Clinical Psychology Review, 30(3), 349–362

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holton, R. (2014). Intention as a model of belief. In V. Manuel & Y. Gideon (Eds.), Rational and social agency: Essays on the philosophy of Michael Bratman.Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, A. (2012). Two ways to put knowledge first. The Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90(2), 353–369

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, A. (2016). From relative truth to finean non-factualism. Synthese, 193(3), 971–989

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, A. (2019). Rampant non-factualism: A metaphysical framework and its treatment of vagueness. Analytic Philosophy, 60(2), 79–108

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, D. R., Cushman, G. K., Borden, L. A., & McCune, M. S. (2013). Potentiating empathic growth: Generating imagery while reading fiction increases empathy and prosocial behavior. Psychology of Aesthetics, Creativity, and the Arts, 7(3), 306–312

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2003). A perspective on judgment and choice: Mapping bounded rationality. American Psychologist, 58(9), 697–720

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kobayashi, H., & Kohshima, S. (1997). Unique morphology of the human eye. Nature, 387(6635), 767–768

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kruglanski, A. W., & Webster, D. M. (1996). Motivated closing of the mind: “Seizing” and “Freezing.” Psychological Review, 103(2), 263–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ledgerwood, A. (2014). Evaluations in their social context: Distance regulates consistency and context dependence. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 8, 436–447

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. The Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74(4), 549–567

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liberman, N., & Trope, Y. (2014). Traversing psychological distance. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 18(7), 364–369

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2014). Assessment sensitivity: Relative truth and its applications. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mayseless, O., & Kruglanski, A. W. (1987). What makes you so sure? Effects of epistemic motivations on judgmental confidence. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 39(2), 162–183

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, R. (2013). ‘Knowledge’ascriptions, social roles and semantics. Episteme, 10(4), 335–350

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, R., & Cushman, F. (2013). Aversive for me, wrong for you: First-person behavioral aversions underlie the moral condemnation of harm. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 7(10), 707–718

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mrkva, K., Travers, M., & Van Boven, L. (2018). Simulational fluency reduces feelings of psychological distance. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 147(3), 354–376

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, J. (2010). Epistemic anxiety and adaptive invariantism. Philosophical Perspectives, 24, 407–435

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, J. (2012). Mindreading in gettier cases and sceptical pressure cases. In J. Brown & M. Gerken (Eds.), Knowledge ascriptions (pp. 171–191). Oxford University Press.

  • Newell, B., & Lee, M. (2011). The right tool for the job? Comparing an evidence accumulation and a naive strategy selection model of decision making. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 24(5), 456–481

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nook, E. C., Schleider, J. L., & Somerville, L. H. (2017). A linguistic signature of psychological distancing in emotion regulation. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 146(3), 337–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Open Science Collaboration. (2015). Estimating the reproducibility of psychological science. Science 349(6251), acc4716.

  • Payne, J., & Bettman, J. (2004). Walking with the scarecrow: The information-processing approach to decision research. In D. Koehler & N. Harvey (Eds.), Blackwell handbook of judgment and decision making. Blackwell.

  • Pearson, J., Naselaris, T., Holmes, E. A., & Kosslyn, S. M. (2015). Mental imagery: functional mechanisms and clinical applications. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 19(10), 590–602

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peetz, J., Wilson, A. E., & Strahan, E. J. (2009). So far away: The role of subjective temporal distance to future goals in motivation and behavior. Social Cognition, 27(4), 475–495

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinillos, N. Á. (2011). Some recent work in experimental epistemology. Philosophy Compass, 6(10), 675–688

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinillos, N. Á. (2012). Knowledge, experiments and practical interests. In J. Brown & M. Gerken (Eds.), Knowledge Ascriptions. Oxford University Press.

  • Pinillos, N. Á., & Simpson, S. (2014). Experimental evidence supporting anti-intellectualism about knowledge. In J. Beebe (Ed.), Advances in experimental epistemology. (pp. 9–44). Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Powell, D., Horne, Z., Pinillos, N. Á., & Holyoak, K. J. (2015). A Bayesian framework for knowledge attribution: Evidence from semantic integration. Cognition, 139, 92–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliff, R., & McKoon, G. (2008). The diffusion decision model: Theory and data for two-choice decision tasks. Neural Computation, 20(4), 873–922

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roets, A., Van Hiel, A., Cornelis, I., & Soetens, B. (2008). Determinants of task performance and invested effort: A need for closure by relative cognitive capacity interaction analysis. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 34(6), 779–792

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rose, D., Machery, E., Stich, S., Alai, M., Angelucci, A., Berniūnas, R., Buchtel, E. E., Chatterjee, A., Cheon, H., Cho, I. R., Cohnitz, D., et al. (2019). Nothing at stake in knowledge. Nous, 51(1), 224–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rysiew, P. (2007). Speaking of knowing. Nous, 41(4), 627–662

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schilbach, L., Timmermans, B., Reddy, V., Costall, A., Bente, G., Schlicht, T., & Vogeley, K. (2013). Toward a second-person neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 393–462

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, N. (2007). Attitude construction: Evaluation in context. Social Cognition 25(5), 638–656.

  • Shea, N., Boldt, A., Bang, D., Yeung, N., Heyes, C., & Frith, C. D. (2014). Supra-personal cognitive control and metacognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 18(4), 186–193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simen, P., Contreras, D., Buck, C., Hu, P., Holmes, P., & Cohen, J. D. (2009). Reward rate optimization in two-alternative decision making: Empirical tests of theoretical predictions. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 35(6), 1865–1897.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. (1956). Rational choice and the structure of the environment. Psychological Review, 63, 129–138

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, E. R., & Semin, G. R. (2004). Socially situated cognition: Cognition in its social context. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 36, 57–121

    Google Scholar 

  • Soderberg, C. K., Callahan, S. P., Kochersberger, A. O., Amit, E., & Ledgerwood, A. (2015). The effects of psychological distance on abstraction: Two meta-analyses. Psychological Bulletin, 141(3), 525–548

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Söllner, A., Bröder, A., Glöckner, A., & Betsch, T. (2014). Single-process versus multiple-strategy models of decision making: Evidence from an information intrusion paradigm. Acta Psychologica, 146, 84–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sripada, C. S., & Stanley, J. (2012). Empirical tests of interest-relative invariantism. Episteme, 9(1), 3–26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Staffel, J. (2013). Can there be reasoning with degrees of belief? Synthese, 190(16), 3535–3551

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Staffel, J. (2019). How do beliefs simplify reasoning? Nous, 53(4), 937–962

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Standage, D., Gunnar B., Michael D. (2014). On the neural implementation of the speed-accuracy trade-off. Frontiers in Neuroscience, 8, 236.

  • Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2012). The Evolved Apprentice. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tetlock, P. (2002). Social functionalist frameworks for judgment and choice: Intuitive politicians, theologians, and prosecutors. Psychological Review, 109(3), 451–471

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2009). Why we cooperate. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Trautmann, S. T. (2019). Distance from a distance: the robustness of psychological distance effects. Theory and Decision, 87, 1–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trope, Y., & Liberman, N. (2010). Construal-level theory of psychological distance. Psychological Review, 117, 440–463

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2017). Epistemic contextualism: An idle hypothesis. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 95(1), 141–156

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J., Buckwalter, W., & Rose, D. (2016). Actionability judgments cause knowledge judgments. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 5(3), 212–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Boven, L., & Caruso, E. M. (2015). The tripartite foundations of temporal psychological distance: Metaphors, ecology, and teleology. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 9(11), 593–605

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Boven, L., Kane, J., McGraw, A. P., & Dale, J. (2010). Feeling close: Emotional intensity reduces perceived psychological distance. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 98(6), 872–885.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Laer, T., De Ruyter, K., Visconti, L. M., & Wetzels, M. (2014). The extended transportation-imagery model: A meta-analysis of the antecedents and consequences of consumers’ narrative transportation. Journal of Consumer Research, 40(5), 797–817

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagenmakers, E. J. (2009). Methodological and empirical developments for the Ratcliff diffusion model of response times and accuracy. European Journal of Cognitive Psychology, 21(5), 641–671.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warneken, F. (2015). Precocious prosociality: Why do young children help? Child Development Perspectives, 9(1), 1–6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weatherson, B. (2012). Knowledge, bets, and interests. In J. Brown & M. Gerken (Eds.), Knowledge ascriptions. Oxford University Press.

  • Weisberg, J. (2016). Belief in psyontology. Philosophers’ Imprint, 20(11), 1–27.

  • Wessler, J., & Hansen, J. (2016). The effect of psychological distance on automatic goal contagion. Comprehensive Results in Social Psychology, 1(1–3), 51–85

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wickelgren, W. A. (1977). Speed-accuracy tradeoff and information processing dynamics. Acta Psychologica, 41(1), 67–85

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2005). Contextualism, subject-sensitive invariantism, and knowledge of knowledge. The Philosophical Quarterly, 55(219), 213–235

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yeh, W., & Barsalou, L. (2006). The situated nature of concepts. American Journal of Psychology, 119(3), 349–384

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank the following for helpful conversations and feedback on earlier drafts: Anne Bosse, Andrew Cortens, Stephen Crowley, Chris Frith, Nat Hansen, Richard Holton, Brian Kierland, Rae Langton, Edouard Machery, Benjamin Marschall, Lucy McDonald, Jennifer Nagel, Ángel Pinillos, Baron Reed, David Rose, William Skylark, Jonathan Weisberg, and three anonymous referees for this journal. I would also like to thank the organizers and audiences at the Buffalo Experimental Philosophy Conference (2017), the Joint Session of the Aristotelian Society and the Mind Association (2017), the BARSEA epistemology workshop (2017), and the APA Central Division meeting (2016).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alexander Jackson.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Jackson, A. Are knowledge ascriptions sensitive to social context?. Synthese 199, 8579–8610 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03176-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03176-7

Keywords

Navigation