Elsevier

Cognition

Volume 106, Issue 2, February 2008, Pages 913-923
Cognition

Discussion
On prototypes as defaults (Comment on Connolly, Fodor, Gleitman and Gleitman, 2007),☆☆

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2007.02.009Get rights and content

Introduction

In an interesting contribution to research on conceptual combination, Connolly, Fodor, Gleitman, and Gleitman (2007) (CFGG) tested a hypothesis that they identified as a common assumption of prototype models of conceptual combination, ‘the crucial default to the stereotype prediction’ (DS). Defaulting to the stereotype consists in assuming, barring information to the contrary, that the prototype corresponding to an adjective noun combination (AN), fully inherits the properties of the prototype corresponding to the noun (N) of that combination. For instance, the prototype corresponding to uncomfortable sofa should share all the properties of the sofa prototype, except for those properties that have to do with comfort. In contradiction of this hypothesis, they reported an experiment in which people’s willingness to accept that a property is true of the members of some class tended to be lower when the concept was modified (uncomfortable sofas have backrests) than when it was unmodified (sofas have backrests). According to CFGG, since all prototype models of conceptual combination require DS to be true, the empirical demonstration that DS fails should be taken as important evidence against the correctness of such models.

Prior to reporting their experimental results, CFGG offered an argument to the effect that DS is in any case non-optimal and ‘invites indefinitely many bad bets’. Thus, according to CFGG, prototype theory embraces a misleading strategy, liable to lead people to make false inferences about the properties of complex concepts. Together, the empirical demonstration that people do not follow DS and the argument that DS is a bad strategy provide sufficient reason to favor some form of the ‘classical’ model over prototype models as the best approach to conceptual combination. The model they favor involves the assumption that (in the default case) modifiers and nouns correspond to concepts which are combined without being transformed into a structure having both of the original concepts as parts, so that the concept LITHUANIAN HAIR corresponds simply to a structure having the concepts LITHUANIAN and HAIR as parts. The classical combinatorial process involves no propagation of the prototypical/stereotypical properties of HAIR to LITHUANIAN HAIR although world knowledge may be evoked post-combination in order to make informed judgments about the likely properties of the complex concept.

Our paper aims to shed additional light on this topic, first by drawing out the implications of some recently published data that has explored and extended CFGG’s empirical result, and then by considering a number of important points in their paper. We disagree with them on several counts. First, we show that the results they report greatly exaggerate the extent to which subjects actually refrain from using the DS strategy. In fact when given the opportunity, most of the time people choose to say that a property is equally likely of a modified as of an unmodified noun, even when two atypical modifiers are used. Second, many of the prototype models that they claim to discredit do not embody the DS strategy at all, certainly not in the sense of rigidly defaulting to the stereotype regardless of the influence of knowledge-based inferences. Third, the results they report, contrary to undermining a central property of prototype approaches to conceptual combination, actually support a thesis that all these approaches do have in common – that the prototypes corresponding to complex expressions depend on the prototypes corresponding to their parts. Fourth, their argument that DS is an inefficient strategy is weak, and an alternative principled argument is offered for why in fact one should use this strategy. Our argument goes further in justifying why confidence in the inheritance of default attributes should be moderated by the typicality of the modifier – a point in their data that CFGG do not directly address.

We will argue for each of these points separately in the following sections. The final section argues that their results provide little reason to prefer the classical approach over the prototype approach to conceptual combination.

Section snippets

DS is the most common strategy for interpreting modifier-noun phrases

In support of their claim that subjects do not follow the DS strategy, CFGG reported a study in which people judged a bare plural generic sentence asserting a property of a class (Ns are P) to be more likely to be true than the same sentence when the noun was modified by an adjective or noun (MNs are P). So, for instance, people rated the sentence Penguins live in cold climates more likely to be true than the sentence Solitary penguins live in cold climates. Modifiers lowered sentence

The classical model versus the prototype model of conceptual combination

The model of conceptual combination that CFGG favored, the classical model, is one where “concepts remain inert under combination” (CFGG, p. 2), and “all you get from your concepts and combinatorics is output denoting relations among sets, properties, or individuals (depending on the ontology assumed)” (p. 4). In contrast to prototype theory, their model of conceptual combination does not presuppose that concepts have internal structure or that the result of combination is some transformation

First page preview

First page preview
Click to open first page preview

References (20)

There are more references available in the full text version of this article.

Cited by (22)

  • Conceptual composition: The role of relational competition in the comprehension of modifier-noun phrases and noun-noun compounds

    2013, Psychology of Learning and Motivation - Advances in Research and Theory
    Citation Excerpt :

    In the modification effect paradigm, participants judge the likely truth of a feature for a modified noun (e.g. baby ducks have webbed feet) or for the noun itself (e.g. ducks have webbed feet). The result is that the judgments are lower for the modified noun than for the noun (Connolly et al., 2007; Gagné & Spalding, 2011; Jönsson & Hampton, 2008). While the empirical result is robust, three different theoretical explanations have arisen.

  • Inferential processing and meta-knowledge as the bases for property inclusion in combined concepts

    2011, Journal of Memory and Language
    Citation Excerpt :

    Connolly et al. (2007) propose that the inheritance view predicts that the ratings to the unmodified and modified versions would be equivalent. In contrast, Jönsson and Hampton (2008) claim that the inheritance view predicts that the ratings for the modified version would be reduced because, according to the selective modification model, the salience of the dimension affected by the modification would increase and, thereby, the relative salience of other dimensions would decrease. However, as discussed in the Introduction, this prediction does not correspond to the model because increasing the weight of the modified dimension does not affect the weights of dimensions that are not affected by the modification (see examples provided by Smith et al., 1988).

  • The modifier effect and property mutability

    2011, Journal of Memory and Language
    Citation Excerpt :

    It has been argued (e.g. by Connolly et al. (2007)) that the modifier effect is evidence against such models, since according to this model, while the dimension HABITAT receives additional weight, other prototypical properties of the concept which are unrelated to habitat (such as [COLOR = black]) should remain in the schema unchanged. Jönsson and Hampton (2008) pointed to a number of problems with this argument. For example, given that habitat now has extra importance, and assuming that importance is a relative measure, other properties must then have reduced importance, which would lead to a general modifier effect.2

  • On the notion of concept II

    2009, Artificial Intelligence
  • The Oxford handbook of the mental lexicon

    2022, The Oxford Handbook of the Mental Lexicon
View all citing articles on Scopus

This manuscript was accepted under the editorship of Jacques Mehler.

☆☆

The authors acknowledge the financial support of City University, London, and Erik and Gurli Hultengrens’s Foundation for Philosophy (Sweden). We wish to thank Pernilla Asp, John Barry, Herbert Clark, Zachary Estes, Daniel Heussen and Lena Wahlberg for fruitful discussions of the research and comments on the manuscript. The authors contributed equally to the research.

View full text