John Dee on geometry: Texts, teaching and the Euclidean tradition

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2011.12.005Get rights and content

Abstract

John Dee’s mathematical interests have principally been studied through his Mathematicall praeface to Henry Billingsley’s 1570 translation of Euclid’s Elements. The focus here is broadened to include the notes he added to Books X–XIII of the Elements. I argue that this additional material drew on a manuscript text, the Tyrocinium mathematicum, that Dee wrote a decade earlier, probably as tutor to the youthful Thomas Digges. Using new evidence for this now-lost work, as well as his notes on Euclid, makes it possible to clarify Dee’s approach to geometry. The contrasting positions adopted by his Parisian acquaintance Petrus Ramus also illuminate Dee’s geometrical choices and values. Unlike Ramus, Dee was not a pugnacious advocate of radical reform, yet he did look beyond the limits of Euclid’s geometry towards deeper disciplinary visions of knowledge. The first published work of his pupil Thomas Digges not only suggests how Dee shaped the younger man’s work but also reflects fresh light back on Dee’s own programme for a ‘more general art Mathematical.’

Introduction

In his Mathematicall praeface to the 1570 English Euclid, John Dee places great stress on the fundamental role of arithmetic and geometry. They lead upwards to the contemplations of pure intellect and downwards to productive engagement with the natural world, serving as the source and root of a whole spectrum of ‘arts mathematical derivative.’ Strangely, given the scholarship that has been devoted to the Mathematicall praeface and to Dee’s active pursuit of various practical mathematical arts, remarkably little attention has been given to his treatment of these two principal mathematical sciences.1

In this paper I want to focus on Dee’s approach to geometry, both to identify his intellectual position and to assess his significance and impact. Twenty years on from its publication, my principal point of reference is Nicholas Clulee’s John Dee’s natural philosophy (1988). Faced with the terrifyingly broad field of Dee’s intellectual formation and disciplinary ambition, Clulee’s work represents a model of scholarship—integrating biography and the pursuit of patronage with the careful analysis of intellectual development and affiliation. He always seeks to pinpoint Dee’s sources with precision rather than constantly invoking a single overarching explanatory theme (whether Neoplatonism, Renaissance magic, Hermeticism, or any other all- encompassing interpretative term).

Clulee’s attention was centred on Dee’s natural philosophy and his position within the history of science. Although the Mathematicall praeface appears as one of his key texts, Dee’s mathematics enters the account primarily for the light it sheds on these central issues. Here I attempt a similar style of analysis, but take Dee’s geometry as worthy of study in its own right. This means giving close and serious attention to his writings, both surviving and lost, and establishing them within the chronological framework of Dee’s career, while also being alert to wider resonances and responses.

Textbook histories of mathematics have typically focused on the innovations of algebra as the central development of the Renaissance. Judged against transhistorical (or even ‘eternal’) criteria of mathematical significance, sixteenth-century geometry has been considered a static or even stagnant field.2 Bennett (2002) has responded to ‘the baneful influence of timelessness’ in the history of Renaissance mathematics by shifting attention to practical geometry, to the vigorous world of instruments and practice. A full account of Dee’s geometry would have to address that broad field, to encompass his inventions and devices for astronomy, navigation, geography and much else. But the realm of texts and scholarship need not be entirely abandoned: far from the cliché of stagnation, geometry was in reality culturally dynamic and diverse. Ancient authorities were not only textually recovered and renewed, but also reworked, supplemented and even attacked. Rather than a placid backwater, geometry was a field pockmarked by active debate and controversy, most famously on the quadrature of the circle.3 Dee was familiar with most of these cross-currents, both through his extraordinarily rich library and his personal acquaintance with many of the leading mathematicians of Europe. By locating him within this contemporary mathematical landscape we can recover what was at stake in the pursuit and teaching of geometry, and see how his mathematical values encouraged the work of others.

Rather than dwelling exclusively on the familiar terrain of Dee’s Mathematicall praeface, I want to take as my point of departure the notes he added to Euclid’s Elements. In the Compendious rehearsal’s listing of the printed and manuscript works produced during his fifty years of study, Dee gave these additions a separate record from the entry for the Mathematicall praeface. He described them as ‘divers & many Annotations, and Inventions Mathematicall, added in sundry places of the foresaid English Euclide, after the tenth Booke of the same.’4 They are scattered throughout Books X to XIII and, while not adding up to a connected work, they do represent a significant investment of time.5 I argue that these comments drew on a manuscript text, the Tyrocinium mathematicum, that Dee wrote a decade earlier, probably as tutor to the youthful Thomas Digges. Using new evidence for this now-lost work together with his notes on Euclid makes it possible to clarify Dee’s approach to geometry, particularly when illuminated by the contrasting positions adopted by his Parisian acquaintance Petrus Ramus. Unlike Ramus, Dee was not a pugnacious advocate of radical reform, yet he did look beyond the limits of Euclid’s geometry towards deeper disciplinary visions of knowledge. The first published work of his pupil Thomas Digges not only suggests how Dee shaped the younger man’s work but also reflects fresh light back on Dee’s own programme for a ‘more general art Mathematical.’ Situating Dee in his contemporary context provides vital insight, but I conclude that in many respects Dee was continuing well- established traditions of medieval geometry, just as he did in natural philosophy.

Section snippets

Printing and writing

The hurried and harassed tone of Dee’s Mathematicall praeface has often been noted. Dee refers several times to being ‘pinched with straightnes of tyme’: ‘the Printer, hath looked for this Praeface, a day or two’ and ‘still the Printer awayting, for my pen staying.’6 Dee was not exaggerating the urgency of his composition. The preface was completed on 9 February 1570, a few days after he had finished the striking tabular ‘Groundplat’ on the 3rd.

Tyrocinium mathematicum

Billingsley’s Euclid in fact gives us a candidate for the role of Dee’s source text. It appears in a note that must at least have been authorised if not actually authored by Dee himself. The comment appears deep in the theory of irrational magnitudes at Book X, 53, and follows a corollary translated from the 1566 Latin edition of François Foix de Candale (Flussas). It is accompanied by a marginal note, ‘M. Dee his booke called Tyrocinium Mathematicum’, and although it has been cited before, is

The challenge of Ramus

One area in which we can be confident of continuity between the Tyrocinium mathematicum and Dee’s additions to Euclid is his work on Book X of the Elements. This sustained interest may in itself seem unremarkable, particularly given the notorious difficulty of the book. But Dee’s attention came at a very specific moment, just when Book X became the starting point for a vigorous and divisive programme of mathematical reform.

Beyond Euclid

If Dee acted against Ramus as a loyal defender of Euclid and ancient geometry, he was not a slavish adherent. As has been recognised before, Dee looked beyond the limits and prescriptions which are embodied in Euclid’s Elements (Dee, 1978, p. 27). We might indeed see Dee’s career as a succession of attempts to overcome conventional demarcations so as to reach a more profound and universal insight than provided by ordinary arts. Geometry has a special status in this process since it provided a

Dee and Digges

From the exploration of the further frontiers and more elusive ambitions of Dee’s enterprise, I want to come back down to a more readily documented dimension of his contribution to the culture of geometry. I argued above that the Tyrocinium mathematicum had been prepared as part of Dee’s tuition of Thomas Digges. Having identified the connections between that lost work and Dee’s additions to Euclid, and recovered something of Dee’s place within the contemporary field of mathematics, we can now

Conclusion

The Tyrocinium mathematicum of 1559 dates from an intense period in Dee’s mathematical career. In the same year that he published the Propaedeumata aphoristica of 1558, he wrote the De speculis comburentibus, part of which survives as a study of the geometry of the parabola. It was in 1559 that he deciphered and made the fresh copy of the medieval Latin translation of Machometus Bagdedinus’s On the division of figures that he would give to Commandino in 1563 (Rose, 1972). We have seen that the

References (51)

  • J. Hogendijk

    The scholar and the fencing master: the exchanges between Joseph Justus Scaliger and Ludolph van Ceulen on the circle quadrature (1594–1596)

    Historia Mathematica

    (2010)
  • A. Malet

    Renaissance notions of number and magnitude

    Historia Mathematica

    (2006)
  • B. Almeida

    On the origins of Dee’s mathematical programme: the John Dee-Pedro Nunes connection

    Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science Part A

    (2011)
  • R.C. Archibald

    The first translation of Euclid’s “Elements” into English and its source

    The American Mathematical Monthly

    (1950)
  • J. Bennett

    Geometry in context in the sixteenth century: the view from the museum

    Early Science and Medicine

    (2002)
  • P. Bockstaele

    Between Viète and Descartes: Adriaan van Roomen and the “mathesis universalis”

    Archive for History of Exact Sciences

    (2009)
  • H. Bos

    Redefining geometrical exactness: Descartes’ transformation of the early modern concept of construction

    (2001)
  • F. Cajori

    A history of mathematics

    (1991)
  • Calder, I. R. F. (1952). John Dee studied as an English neoplatonist (2 Vols.). Ph.D. dissertation, Warburg Institute,...
  • M. Casaubon

    A true & faithful relation of what passed for many yeers between Dr. John Dee . . . and some spirits

    (1659)
  • M. Clagett

    Archimedes in the Middle Ages. Vol. 4: A supplement on medieval Latin translations of conic sections (1150–1566)

    (1980)
  • S. Clucas

    Mathematics and humanism in Elizabethan England

    Journal de la Renaissance

    (2006)
  • N.H. Clulee

    John Dee’s natural philosophy: between science and religion

    (1988)
  • F. Commandino

    De superficierum divisionibus liber Machometo Bagdedino ascriptus

    (1570)
  • de Wreede, L. C. (2007). Willebrord Snellius (1580–1626): A humanist reshaping the mathematical sciences. Ph.D....
  • de Wreede, L. C. (2010). A dialogue on the use of arithmetic in geometry: Van Ceulen’s and Snellius’s “Fundamenta...
  • J. Dee

    Propaedeumata aphoristica

    (1568)
  • Dee, J. (1570). Mathematicall praeface. In Euclid...
  • J. Dee

    Parallaticae commentationis praxeosq[ue] nucleus quidam

    (1573)
  • J. Dee

    A letter, containing a most briefe discourse apologeticall

    (1599)
  • Dee, J. (1726). The compendious rehearsal. In T. Hearne (Ed.), Johannis, fratris & monachis Glastoniensis, chronica (2...
  • J. Dee

    John Dee on astronomy: “Propaedeumata aphoristica” (1558 and 1568), Latin and English

    (1978)
  • T. Digges

    A geometricall practise, named Pantometria

    (1571)
  • T. Digges

    Alae seu scalae mathematicae

    (1573)
  • Euclid

    The elements of geometry of Euclid of Megara

    (1570)
  • Cited by (9)

    • On the origins of Dee's mathematical programme: The John Dee-Pedro Nunes connection

      2012, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A
      Citation Excerpt :

      In his Compendious rehearsal (1592), and again in a letter to the Archbishop of Canterbury (1599), he claims to have completed a work in 1560 on the areas of plane triangles—De Triangulorum rectilineorum Areis35—dedicated to the ‘excellentissimum Mathematicum’, Pedro Nunes. In his essay in this volume, Stephen Johnston establishes an interesting connection between this work on triangle areas and another lost work, named Tyrocinium mathematicum, also dedicated to Nunes (Johnston, 2011). These dedications may point to a broader recognition of the Portuguese cosmographer’s mathematical work, perhaps even to a quest for some kind of ‘intellectual patronage.’

    • The Main Figures: From Recorde to Wallis and Barrow

      2022, SpringerBriefs in History of Science and Technology
    • Philosophical Algebra

      2020, International Archives of the History of Ideas/Archives Internationales d'Histoire des Idees
    • “The marriage of physics with mathematics”: Francis Bacon on measurement, mathematics, and the construction of a mathematical physics

      2016, The Language of Nature: Reassessing the Mathematization of Natural Philosophy in the 17th Century
    View all citing articles on Scopus
    View full text