Skip to main content
Log in

Moral Deficits, Moral Motivation and the Feasibility of Moral Bioenhancement

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The debate over moral bioenhancement has incrementally intensified since 2008, when Persson and Savulescu, and Douglas wrote two separate articles on the reasons why enhancing human moral capabilities and sensitivity through technological means was ethically desirable. In this article, we offer a critique of how Persson and Savulescu theorize about the possibility of moral bioenhancement, including the problem of weakness of will, which they see as a motivational challenge. First, we offer a working definition of moral bioenhancement and underscore some of the challenges in determining whether moral bioenhancement, as conceptualized by Persson and Savulescu, falls into the category of enhancement or constitutes a type of therapeutic intervention. Second, we provide a critical analysis of the way Persson and Savulescu pathologize human behavior in relation to what they see as the main threat to the survival of the human species: weak moral motivation. Next, we critique the claim that the use of genetic manipulation and drug treatment will increase moral motivation. We argue that Persson and Savulescu mischaracterize the nature of human moral psychology because moral motivation includes affective and cognitive dimensions. The type of interventions they envision focus almost exclusively on the former. In the final two sections, we outline three main criticisms of moral bioenhancement and offer a more robust account of moral psychology and moral development than what Persson and Savulescu recommend, through the lens of Aristotle’s work on virtue ethics. Ultimately, we argue that what Persson and Savulescu, and Douglas consider as moral bioenhancement is a misnomer because they do not fully account for the complexity of moral agency.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. On the distinction of oxytocin from “classical neurotransmitters,” see Bethlehem et al. (2013, p. 964).

  2. The overall results concerning citalopram are, however, mixed. According to Kamarck et al. (2009, p. 184), the drug lowers hostility on the part of subjects “with initially elevated hostility scores,” as gauged by subjects’ self-assessments. Such a phenomenon is quite different from and may not lead to an augmentation of actively prosocial feelings and conduct. Further, per the findings of Crockett et al. (2010, p. 17436), citalopram heightens empathy “by boosting an already-present neural signal…rather than being the source of empathic responses.”

  3. For discussion of biomedical enhancement within the normal range of human capacities, see Kahane and Savulescu (2015). The focus of their analysis is “forms of biomedical enhancement that are almost certainly feasible, and in fact likely to be available soon – the forms of enhancement that operate within the existing range of human capacities and dispositions. We call this normal range human enhancement” (p. 133).

  4. The use of therapeutic language reflects the pathologizing of human behavior. Persson and Savulescu (2012, p. 107) state that “it is th[e] motivational internalization of moral doctrines that we think could be sped up by means which the scientific exploration of the genetic and neurobiological bases of our behaviour might put into our hands. We call moral enhancement by such means moral bioenhancement; possible examples of moral bioenhancement would be drug treatment and genetic engineering.”

  5. For a critique of a neuroreductionistic approach to morality, see Jotterand (2016).

  6. Emotion on its own can lead to behavior that is defective in various other ways, too: short-sighted from a prudential standpoint, as in giving well beyond one’s means due to a surge of pity; disproportionate to the impetus, for instance, rushing heedlessly into a burning building to rescue an important but replaceable item or becoming enraged and lashing out, rather than simply being disappointed, if someone else receives a prize that one had sought; escapism via, e.g., powerful nostalgia; and consumption by jealousy or envy, issuing in conduct that is destructive to oneself and others.

  7. For this reason, Woodward declines to use “reason” and “cognition” interchangeably: on his account, both brain areas focused on reason and those devoted to “emotional processing…are doing ‘cognitive’ processing simply in virtue of doing information processing” (2016, p. 114n9).

  8. For Aristotle’s bearing, by way of critique, on advocacy of vigorous cognitive enhancement, see Levin (2017).

  9. Translations of the Nicomachean Ethics are from Ostwald (1962), with some adjustments; line numbers are those of Bywater (1894).

References

  • Bethlehem RAI, Honk J van, Auyeung B, Baron-Cohen S (2013) Oxytocin, brain physiology, and functional connectivity: a review of intranasal oxytocin fMRI studies. Psychoneuroendocrinology 38(7):962–974

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blair RJR (2001) Neurocognitive models of aggression, the antisocial personality disorders, and psychopathy. J Neurol Neurosurg Psychiatry 71(6):727–731

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bywater I (ed) (1894) Aristotle, Ethica Nicomachea. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Crockett MJ, Clark L, Hauser MD, Robbins TW (2010) Serotonin selectively influences moral judgment and behavior through effects on harm aversion. Proc Natl Acad Sci 107(40):17433–17438

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas T (2008) Moral enhancement. J Appl Philos 25(3):228–245

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas T (2013) Moral enhancement via direct emotion modulation: a reply to John Harris. Bioethics 27(3):160–168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris J (2011) Moral enhancement and freedom. Bioethics 25(2):102–111

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris J (2013) “Ethics is for bad guys!” Putting the “moral” into moral enhancement. Bioethics 27(3):169–173

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris J (2014) “…How narrow the strait!” The God machine and the spirit of liberty. Camb Q Healthc Ethics 23(3):247–260

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris J (2016a) How to be good: the possibility of moral enhancement. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harris J (2016b) Moral blindness—the gift of the God Machine. Neuroethics. doi:10.1007/s12152-016-9272-9

    Google Scholar 

  • Henry S, Plemmons D (2012) Neuroscience, neuropolitics and neuroethics: the complex case of crime, deception and fMRI. Sci Eng Ethics 18(3):573–591

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jotterand F (2017) Cognitive enhancement of today may be the normal of tomorrow. In: Illes J, Hossain S (eds) Neuroethics: defining the issues in theory, practice and policy, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Jotterand F (2011) Virtue engineering and moral agency: will post-humans still need the virtues? AJOB Neurosci 2(4):3–9

    Google Scholar 

  • Jotterand F (2016) Moral enhancement, neuroessentialism, and moral content. In: Jotterand F, Dubljevic V (eds) Cognitive enhancement: ethical and policy implications in international perspectives. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 42–56

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jotterand F, Giordano J (2015) Real-time functional magnetic resonance imaging (rtfMRI)—brain-computer interfacing in the assessment and treatment of psychopathy: potential and challenges. In: Clausen J, Levy N (eds) Handbook of Neuroethics. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 763–781

    Google Scholar 

  • Jotterand F, Ienca M (2017) The biopolitics of neuroethics. In Racine E, Aspler J (eds) The debate about neuroethics: perspectives on the field’s development, focus, and future. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Juengst ET (1998) What does enhancement mean? In: Parens E (ed) Enhancing human traits: ethical and social implications. Georgetown University Press, Washington DC, pp 29–47

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahane G, Savulescu J (2015) Normal human variation: refocussing the enhancement debate. Bioethics 29(2):133–143

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamarck TW, Haskett RF, Muldoon M, Flory JD, Anderson B, Bies R, Pollock B, Manuck SB (2009) Citalopram intervention for hostility: results of a randomized clinical trial. J Consult Clin Psychol 77(1):174–188

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King LJ (1999) A brief history of psychiatry: millennia past and present. Ann Clin Psychiatry 11(1):3–12

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosfeld M, Heinrichs M, Zak PJ, Fischbacher U, Fehr E (2005) Oxytocin increases trust in humans. Nature 435(7042):673–676

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levin SB (2016) Upgrading discussions of cognitive enhancement. Neuroethics 9(1):53–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levin SB (2017) Enhancing future children: how it might happen, whether it should. In: Campo-Engelstein L, Burcher P (eds) Reproductive ethics: new challenges and conversations. Springer, New York

  • Mele AR (1999) Motivation. In: Audi R (ed) The Cambridge dictionary of philosophy, 2nd edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 591–592

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostwald M, trans (1962) Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Persson I, Savulescu J (2008) The perils of cognitive enhancement and the urgent imperative to enhance the moral character of humanity. J Appl Philos 25(3):162–177

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Persson I, Savulescu J (2012) Unfit for the future: the need for moral enhancement. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Persson I, Savulescu J (2013) Getting moral enhancement right: the desirability of moral bioenhancement. Bioethics 27(3):124–131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Persson I, Savulescu J (2016) Moral bioenhancement, freedom and reason. Neuroethics. doi:10.1007/s12152-016-9268-5

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker S (2011) The better angels of our nature: why violence has declined. Viking/Penguin Group, New York.

  • Sadler JZ (2008) Moral contents and moral capacities: a contribution to understanding relationships between psychopathology and political extremism. Presentation at the 20th Annual Meeting of the Association for the Advancement of Philosophy and Psychiatry, 4 May 2008

  • Savulescu J, Persson J (2012) Moral enhancement, freedom, and the God Machine. Monist 95(3):399–421

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tse WS, Bond AJ (2002) Serotonergic intervention affects both social dominance and affiliative behaviour. Psychopharmacology (Berl) 161(3):324–330

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Urmson JO (1980) Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean. In: Rorty AO (ed) Essays on Aristotle’s ethics. University of California Press, Berkeley, pp 157–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2016) Emotion versus cognition in moral decision-making. In: Liao SM Moral brains: the neuroscience of morality. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 87–116

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Fabrice Jotterand.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Jotterand, F., Levin, S.B. Moral Deficits, Moral Motivation and the Feasibility of Moral Bioenhancement. Topoi 38, 63–71 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9472-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9472-x

Keywords

Navigation