Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Is psychopathy a harmful dysfunction?

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In their paper “Is psychopathy a mental disease?”, Thomas Nadelhoffer and Walter Sinnott-Armstrong argue that according to any plausible account of mental disorder, neural and psychological abnormalities correlated with psychopathy should be regarded as signs of a mental disorder. I oppose this conclusion by arguing that at least on a naturalistically grounded account, such as Wakefield’s ‘Harmful Dysfunction’ view, currently available empirical data and evolutionary considerations indicate that psychopathy is not a mental disorder.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In fact, this question has received little attention across disciplines. In psychology, the notable exceptions are Krupp et al. (2012, 2013) and Leedom and Hartoonian-Almas (2012), while in philosophy, Malatesti (2014) and Reimer (2008) provide preliminary discussions of this issue.

  2. Thanks to two anonymous reviewers for suggesting to be more precise about the scope of my discussion.

  3. In general, it is important to keep in mind that mental disorders in legal proceedings are relevant to the extent that they affect legally relevant abilities of an agent (Jefferson and Sifferd 2018). So not every diagnosis of a mental disorder will be relevant for excusing some behavior. However, since antisocial behavior is strongly correlated with (or according to some it is even a part of) the construct of psychopathy (Hare 2003), then if psychopathy were a disorder, we would have strong grounds for explaining psychopaths’ tendency towards antisocial behavior as effects of legally relevant dysfunctional capacities.

  4. Here and in what follows the intended sense of “abnormality” is statistical and not normative.

  5. In addition, some studies indicate that psychopathic personality traits (Factor 1) can be exhibited without antisocial behavior (Factor 2) (see, e.g. Ishikawa et al. 2001). Accordingly, some authors make a distinction between successful and unsuccessful psychopaths (see Glenn and Raine 2014, ch. 7). However, given that this distinction is still rather contested and neuropsychologically not well-grounded (see Maes and Brazil 2013), I will not rely on it in my discussion.

  6. The most notable account is the Response Modulation Hypothesis developed by Newman and colleagues. For this and other variants of the RMH, see, e.g. Koenigs and Newman (2013).

  7. For a neurobiologically grounded model that attempts to provide a unified account of attentional and affective peculiarities correlated with psychopathy, see Moul et al. (2012).

  8. I follow Nadelhoffer and Sinnott-Armstrong (2013) in using ‘illness’, ‘disease’ and ‘disorder’ interchangeably.

  9. For a thorough discussion of different possible combinations of naturalist and normativist views about mental illness, see Kingma (2014).

  10. It might be objected that N&S-A do not give an exhaustive list of accounts of mental illness. Relevantly for the present discussion, they do not consider evolutionary or functional approaches to psychiatry, according to which some condition might be a consequence of an evolutionary adaptation and still be a disorder (see, e.g. Adriaens and DeBlock 2011; Murphy 2005; Nesse and Williams 1997). For instance, different symptoms of anxiety disorders might have been adaptive in ancestral environments which were presumably more unsecure, lacking in resources, and dangerous. But, in modern environments being overly anxious might lead to maladaptive psychological conditions and behaviors. However, I think that N&S-A rightly do not discuss such approaches to mental disorders. Evolutionary approaches to disorders, insofar as they differ from Boorse’s or Wakefield’s accounts, arguably should be construed as providing “explanatory models of dysfunctional, maladaptive behaviour (…)” (Bolton 2008, pp. 126–127, emphasis added). As such they presuppose criteria of what constitutes a mental disorder rather than determining them (see also Wakefield 1992, p. 374). Thus, in principle one might combine them with normativist, naturalist or hybrid accounts.

  11. This criticism might be resisted. However, given my focus on the Harmful Dysfunction view and space limitations, I will not discuss it. For a more recent defense of the biomedical model, see Boorse (2014). For criticisms and modifications to Boorse’s model, see, for instance, Hausman (2012) and Schwartz (2007).

  12. In other words, according to SE, the function of a trait is conferred to it by past selective processes (Neander 1991). Organisms that had these traits survived and reproduced more than other organisms that did not possess traits with these effects. For an overview of theories of biological function, see, e.g. Garson (2016), Sterelny and Griffths (1999, pp. 220–221).

  13. One question facing selected-effects theories is how far in the evolutionary past one needs to look to determine the function of a trait (see Varga 2015, p. 180, ft. 13). A plausible answer is given by the so-called ‘modern history’ account of function (Godfrey-Smith 1994; see also Sterelny and Griffiths 1999, pp. 218–220). According to this view, the function of a trait is determined by the most recent selective pressures that are responsible for maintaining the trait in a population. For its use in the explication of the concept of disorder, see Griffiths and Matthewson (2018).

  14. For recent defenses of the naturalistic accounts of disease that are structurally similar to Wakefield's HD, see Griffiths and Matthewson (2018) and Matthewson and Griffiths (2017). It should be noted, though, that unlike Wakefield (1992), whose goal is to give a conceptual analysis of the concept of disease, Griffiths and Matthewson (2018) provide an explication in the Carnapian sense or a theoretical regimentation of the concept of disease that will be useful for integrating theoretical and practical research in medicine and related fields.

  15. For other issues and complexities related to inferring the activity of natural selection from the apparent design of a feature, see Gould and Lewontin (1979), Lauder (1996) and Sterelny and Griffiths (1999, Sects. 10.3 and 10.5).

  16. It should be noted that these heritability rates do not mean that the expression of psychopathic traits is genetically determined regardless the environment (Glenn and Raine 2014, p. 23; for a discussion of heritability of antisocial behavior, see Tabery 2014, ch. 7). In fact, heritability rates indicate the proportion of variance of a phenotypic trait that can be attributed to genetic as opposed to environmental factors and these rates are always relative to populations under scrutiny. Thus, it should be kept in mind that the proper explanation of heritability of phenotypic traits, even those that have high heritability rates, will always reflect average genetic and environmental interactions in a sampled population (Tabery 2014). This means that in some individuals genetic factors, while in others environmental conditions will have a greater contribution to exhibiting psychopathic traits (Glenn and Raine 2014, p. 23).

  17. This point is raised by an anonymous reviewer because HD presupposes an etiological theory of function.

  18. Antisocial behavior is often modeled as the cheater (defection) strategy within the prisoner’s dilemma game (Harpending and Sobus 1987). However, some studies model psychopathic traits as implementing the hawk strategy in the dove-hawk game (Colman and Wilson 1997). In the empirical literature, there is evidence that psychopathic personality can be related to both the cheater and hawk strategies (see Book and Quinsey 2004).

  19. Murphy (2005, p. 270) suggests in passing that impulsivity and poor long-term planning might be seen as “adaptive cognitive styles”. I develop this point within the Life History theory in “Life-history strategy and longevity/reproduction trade-offs” Section. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pressing me to address this issue.

  20. Thanks to an anonymous referee for directing my attention to this tension in N&S-A’s discussion.

  21. The argumentation in this section should not be read as separate from the argument that psychopathic traits are maintained by a balancing selection. The LHT is a general framework for theorizing about the adaptive challenges that organisms need to solve across life-cycles to maximize their fitness. LHT presupposes that there is a heritable variability underpinning important LH traits (such as personality traits influencing one’s fitness). Frequency-dependent selection is an important mechanism that might account for such variability across different environments (Penke et al. 2007). In our case, it explains how the heritable variation underlying psychopathic and nonpsychopathic personality traits is maintained in human populations. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for indicating the need to make clearer the connection between LHT and frequency-dependent selection.

References

  • Adriaens PR, De Block A (eds) (2011) Maladapting minds: philosophy, psychiatry, and evolutionary theory. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • American Psychiatric Association (2013) Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5, 5th edn. American Psychiatric Association, Washington, D.C

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aspinwall LG, Brown TR, Tabery J (2012) The double-edged sword: does biomechanism increase or decrease judges’ sentencing of psychopaths? Science 337:846–849

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blair RJ (2007) The amygdala and ventromedial prefrontal cortex in morality and psychopathy. Trends Cognit Sci 11:387–392

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blair RJ (2008) The amygdala and ventromedial prefrontal cortex: functional contributions and dysfunction in psychopathy. Philos Trans R Soc B 363:2557–2565

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blair RJ, Mitchell MG, Blair KS (2005) The psychopath: emotion and the brain. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Blonigen DM, Carlson SR, Krueger RF, Patrick CJ (2003) A twin study of self-reported psychopathic personality traits. Pers Individ Differ 35:179–197

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blonigen DM, Hicks B, Krueger R, Patrick CJ, Iacono W (2005) Psychopathic personality traits: heritability and genetic overlap with internalizing and externalizing pathology. Psychol Med 25:637–648

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolton D (2008) What is mental disorder? An essay in philosophy, science, and values. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Book AS, Quinsey VL (2004) Psychopaths: cheaters or warrior-hawks? Pers Individ Differ 36:33–45

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse C (1977) Health as a theoretical concept. Philos Sci 44:542–573

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse C (2014) A second rebuttal on health. J Med Philos 39:683–724

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brzović Z, Jurjako M, Šustar P (2017) The kindness of psychopaths. Int Stud Philos Sci 31:189–211

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buss DM (2009) How can evolutionary psychology successfully explain personality and individual differences? Perspect Psychol Sci 4:359–366

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright S (1851) Report on the diseases and peculiarities of the negro race. DeBow’s Review XI

  • Colman AM, Wilson CJ (1997) Antisocial personality disorder: an evolutionary game theory analysis. Legal Criminol Psychol 2:23–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooke DJ (1998) Psychopathy across cultures. In: Cooke DJ, Forth AE, Hare RD (eds) Psychopathy: theory, research and implications for society. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 13–46

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper R (2002) Disease. Stud Hist Philos Sci Part C: Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 33:263–282

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Curry O, Chester Jones M, Viding E (2011) The psychopath’s dilemma: the effects of psychopathic personality traits in one-shot games. Pers Individ Differ 50:804–809

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Del Giudice M (2014) An evolutionary life history framework for psychopathology. Psychol Inq 25:261–300

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faucher L (2012) Evolutionary psychiatry and nosology: prospects and limitations. Balt Int Yearb Cognit Logic Commun 7:1–64

    Google Scholar 

  • Fowler KA, Lilienfeld SO (2013) Alternatives to psychopathy checklist-revised. In: Kiehl KA, Sinnott-Armstrong WP (eds) Handbook on psychopathy and law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 34–57

    Google Scholar 

  • Gao Y, Raine A, Chan F, Venables PH, Mednick SA (2010) Early maternal and paternal bonding, childhood physical abuse and adult psychopathic personality. Psychol Med 40:1007–1016

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garson J (2016) A critical overview of biological functions. Springer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glenn AL, Raine A (2014) Psychopathy: an introduction to biological findings and their implications. New York University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glenn AL, Laufer WS, Raine A (2011a) Is it wrong to criminalize and punish psychopaths? Emot Rev 3:302–304

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glenn AL, Kurzban R, Raine A (2011b) Evolutionary theory and psychopathy. Aggress Violent Behav 16:371–380

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gluckman PD, Beedle A, Hanson MA (2009) Principles of evolutionary medicine. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (1994) A modern history theory of functions. Noûs 28:344–362

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ, Lewontin RC (1979) The spandrels of San Marco and the panglossian paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme. Proc R Soc Lond B 205:581–598

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE, Matthewson J (2018) Evolution, dysfunction, and disease: a reappraisal. Br J Philos Sci 69:301–327

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare RD (1999) Without conscience. The Guilford Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare RD (2003) The Hare psychopathy checklist revised, 2nd edn. Multi-Health Systems, Toronto

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare RD (2013) Foreword. In: Kiehl KA, Sinnott-Armstrong WP (eds) Handbook on psychopathy and law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp vii–ix

    Google Scholar 

  • Harpending HC, Sobus J (1987) Sociopathy as an adaptation. Ethol Sociobiol 8:63S–72s

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman DM (2012) Health, naturalism, and functional efficiency. Philos Sci 79:519–541

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoppenbrouwers SS, Bulten BH, Brazil IA (2016) Parsing fear: a reassessment of the evidence for fear deficits in psychopathy. Psychol Bull 142:573–600

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ishikawa SS, Raine A, Lencz T, Bihrle S, Lacasse L (2001) Autonomic stress reactivity and executive functions in successful and unsuccessful criminal psychopaths from the community. J Abnorm Psychol 110:423–432

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jefferson A, Sifferd K (2018) Are psychopaths legally insane? Eur J Anal Philos 14:79–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jonason PK, Koenig BL, Tost J (2010a) Living a fast life: the dark triad and life history theory. Human Nat 21:428–442

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jonason PK, Li NP, Buss DM (2010b) The costs and benefits of the dark triad: implications for mate poaching and mate retention tactics. Pers Individ Differ 48:373–378

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jurjako M, Malatesti L (2016) Instrumental rationality in psychopathy: implications from learning tasks. Philos Psychol 26:717–731

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jurjako M, Malatesti L (2018) Neuropsychology and the criminal responsibility of psychopaths: reconsidering the evidence. Erkenntnis 83:1003–1025

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kacelnik A (2006) Meanings of rationality. In: Hurley S, Nudds M (eds) Rational animals?. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 87–106

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Keller MC, Miller G (2006) Resolving the paradox of common, harmful, heritable mental disorders: which evolutionary genetic models work best? Behav Brain Sci 29:385–404

    Google Scholar 

  • Kendell RE (1975) The concept of disease and its implications for psychiatry. Br J Psychiatry 127:305–315

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiehl KA (2006) A cognitive neuroscience perspective on psychopathy: evidence for paralimbic system dysfunction. Psychiatry Res 142:107–128

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiehl KA, Hoffman MB (2011) The criminal psychopath: history, neuroscience, and economics. Jurimetrics 51:355–397

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiehl KA, Sinnott-Armstrong W (eds) (2013) Handbook on psychopathy and law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kingma E (2014) Naturalism about health and disease: adding nuance for progress. J Med Philos 39:590–608

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koenigs M, Newman JP (2013) The decision making impairment in psychopathy: psychological and neurobiological mechanisms. In: Sinnott-Armstrong WP, Kiehl KA (eds) Handbook on psychopathy and law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 93–106

    Google Scholar 

  • Krupp DB, Sewall LA, Lalumière ML, Sheriff C, Harris GT (2012) Nepotistic patterns of violent psychopathy: evidence for adaptation? Front Psychol 3:1–8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krupp DB, Sewall LA, Lalumière ML, Sheriff C, Harris GT (2013) Psychopathy, adaptation, and disorder. Front Psychol 4:1–5

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lalumière M, Mishra S, Harris GT (2008) In cold blood: the evolution of psychopathy. In: Duntley J, Shackelford TJ (eds) Evolutionary forensic psychology. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 176–197

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Larson CL, Baskin-Sommers AR, Stout DM, Balderston NL, Curtin JJ, Schultz DH, Kiehl KA, Newman JP (2013) The interplay of attention and emotion: top-down attention modulates amygdala activation in psychopathy. Cognit Affect Behav Neurosci 13:757–770

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larsson H, Viding E, Plomin R (2008) Callous-unemotional traits and antisocial behavior: genetic, environmental, and early parenting characteristics. Crim Justice Behav 35:197–211

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Latzman RD, Drislane LE, Hecht LK, Brislin SJ, Patrick CJ, Lilienfeld SO, Freeman HJ, Schapiro SJ, Hopkins WD (2016) A chimpanzee (Pan Troglodytes) model of Triarchic Psychopathy Constructs: development and initial validation. Clin Psychol Sci: J Assoc Psychol Sci 4:50–66

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lauder GV (1996) The argument from design. In: Rose M, Lauder GV (eds) Adaptation. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 55–91

    Google Scholar 

  • Leedom LJ, Hartoonian-Almas L (2012) Is psychopathy a disorder or an adaptation? Front Psychol 3:1–3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lilienfeld SO (2013) Is psychopathy a syndrome? Commentary on Marcus, Fulton, and Edens. Pers Disord: Theory Res Treat 4:85–86

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lykken DT (1995) The antisocial personalities. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale

    Google Scholar 

  • Maes JHR, Brazil IA (2013) No clear evidence for a positive association between the interpersonal-affective aspects of psychopathy and executive functioning. Psychiatry Res 210:1265–1274

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malatesti L (2014) Psychopathy and failures of ordinary doing. Ethics Polit 16:1138–1152

    Google Scholar 

  • Malatesti L, McMillan J (eds) (2010) Responsibility and psychopathy: interfacing law, psychiatry and philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthewson J, Griffiths PE (2017) Biological criteria of disease: four ways of going wrong. J Med Philos 42:447–466

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mealey L (1995) The sociobiology of sociopathy: an integrated evolutionary model. Behav Brain Sci 18:460–485

    Google Scholar 

  • Međedović J, Petrović B, Želeskov-Đorić J, Savić M (2017) Interpersonal and affective psychopathy traits can enhance human fitness. Evolut Psychol Sci 3:306–315

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meloy JR, Book A, Hosker-Field A, Methot-Jones T, Roters J (2018) Social, sexual, and violent predation: are psychopathic traits evolutionarily adaptive? Violence Gend 5:153–165

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mokros A, Menner B, Eisenbarth H, Alpers GW, Lange KW, Osterheider M (2008) Diminished cooperativeness of psychopaths in a prisoner’s dilemma game yields higher rewards. J Abnorm Psychol 117:406–413

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moul C, Killcross S, Dadds MR (2012) A model of differential amygdala activation in psychopathy. Psychol Rev 119:789–806

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy D (2005) Can evolution explain insanity? Biol Philos 20:745–766

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy D (2006) Psychiatry in the scientific image. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy D, Woolfolk RL (2000) The harmful dysfunction analysis of mental disorder. Philos Psychiatry Psychol 7:241–252

    Google Scholar 

  • Nadelhoffer T, Sinnott-Armstrong W (2013) Is psychopathy a mental disease? In: Vincent NA (ed) Neuroscience and legal responsibility. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 229–255

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Neander K (1991) Functions as selected effects: the conceptual analyst’s defense. Philos Sci 58:168–184

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nesse RM (2001) On the difficulty of defining disease: a Darwinian perspective. Med Health Care Philos 4:37–46

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nesse RM, Williams G (1997) Are mental disorders diseases? In: Baron-Cohen S (ed) The maladapted mind: classic readings in evolutionary psychopathology. Psychology Press, Hove, pp 1–22

    Google Scholar 

  • Neumann CS, Hare RD (2008) Psychopathic traits in a large community sample: links to violence, alcohol use, and intelligence. J Consult Clin Psychol 76:893–899

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neumann CS, Hare RD (2010) Psychopathy: assessment and forensic implications. In: Malatesti L, McMillan J (eds) Responsibility and psychopathy: interfacing law, psychiatry and philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 93–124

    Google Scholar 

  • Neumann CS, Schmitt DS, Carter R, Embley I, Hare RD (2012) Psychopathic traits in females and males across the globe. Behav Sci Law 30:557–574

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penke L, Denissen JJA, Miller GF (2007) The evolutionary genetics of personality. Eur J Pers 21:549–587

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Power RA, Kyaga S, Uher R, MacCabe JH, Långström N, Landen M et al (2013) Fecundity of patients with schizophrenia, autism, bipolar disorder, depression, anorexia nervosa, or substance abuse vs their unaffected siblings. JAMA Psychiatry 70:22–30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reimer M (2008) Psychopathy without (the language of) disorder. Neuroethics 1:185–198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rilling JK, Glenn AL, Jairam MR, Pagnoni G, Goldsmith DR, Elfenbein HA, Lilienfeld SO (2007) Neural correlates of social cooperation and non-cooperation as a function of psychopathy. Biol Psychiatry 61:1260–1271

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sadler JZ (2008) Vice and the diagnostic classification of mental disorders: a philosophical case conference. Philos Psychiatry Psychol 15:1–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz PH (2007) Defining dysfunction: natural selection, design, and drawing a line. Philos Sci 74:364–385

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skeem JL, Polaschek DLL, Patrick CJ, Lilienfeld SO (2011) Psychopathic personality: bridging the gap between scientific evidence and public policy. Psychol Sci Public Interest 12:95–162

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stearns SC (1989) Trade-offs in life-history evolution. Funct Ecol 3:259–268

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stearns SC (2000) Life history evolution: successes, limitations, and prospects. Naturwissenschaften 87:476–486

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K, Griffiths PE (1999) Sex and death: an introduction to philosophy of biology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Szasz TS (1961) The myth of mental illness. Am Psychol 15:113–118

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tabery J (2014) Beyond versus: the struggle to understand the interaction of nature and nurture. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Varga S (2015) Naturalism, interpretation, and mental disorder. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Viding E, Blair RJR, Moffitt TE, Plomin R (2005) Evidence for substantial genetic risk for psychopathy in 7-year-olds. J Child Psychol Psychiatry 46:592–597

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viding E, Jones A, Frick PJ, Moffitt TE, Plomin R (2008) Heritability of antisocial behaviour at nine-years: do callous-unemotional traits matter? Dev Sci 11:17–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vieira JB, Almeida PR, Ferreira-Santos F, Barbosa F, Marques-Teixeira J, Marsh AA (2014) Distinct neural activation patterns underlie economic decisions in high and low psychopathy scorers. Soc Cognit Affect Neurosci 9:1099–1107

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield JC (1992) The concept of mental disorder: on the boundary between biological facts and social values. Am Psychol 47:373–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield JC (2000) Spandrels, vestigial organs, and such: reply to Murphy and Woolfolk’s “The Harmful Dysfunction analysis of mental disorder”. Philos Psychiatry Psychol 7:253–270

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield JC (2011a) DSM-5 proposed diagnostic criteria for sexual paraphilias: tensions between diagnostic validity and forensic utility. Int J Law Psychiatry 34:195–209

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield JC (2011b) Darwin, functional explanation, and the philosophy of psychiatry. In: Adriaens RA, De Block A (eds) Maladapting minds: philosophy, psychiatry, and evolutionary theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 143–172

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank Justin Garson, Luca Malatesti, Zdenka Brzović, and Janko Međedović for reading and giving valuable comments on previous versions of this paper. I am grateful to two anonymous reviewers of Biology and Philosophy for giving extensive and very useful comments. Thanks also to the University of Rijeka for supporting early career researchers (small Grant 17.05.2.2.04). This paper is an output of project Harm, Intentions, and Responsibility (HIRe) that is financed by the Croatian Science Foundation (Grant HRZZ-UIP-2017-05-4308).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marko Jurjako.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Jurjako, M. Is psychopathy a harmful dysfunction?. Biol Philos 34, 5 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-018-9668-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-018-9668-5

Keywords

Navigation