Skip to main content
Log in

Facts and values in politics and Searle's Construction of Social Reality

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Contemporary Political Theory Aims and scope

Abstract

Contemporary political theory is fractured in its account of ontology and methods. One prominent fault line is between empirical and normative theory – the former usually called ‘philosophy of social science’, or ‘social-science methodology’, and not ‘theory’ at all. A second fault line exists between analytical and post-modern (or ‘late-modern’) political theory. These fractures prevent political researchers who engage with the same substantive issues, such as the right of same-sex couples to marry, from speaking to one another in a common language. This paper's first section discusses the history of the fact-value divide in political studies: a history that led to the contemporary state of the discipline. The second section argues that Searle's philosophy provides tools that can bridge this divide. The third section raises normative objections that limit the extent to which one can accept Searle's theory as a fully general account of social and political reality. Although limited in scope, Searle's argument should be welcomed as an attempt to provide a common set of important tools for political researchers on all sides of these debates.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For more on the correspondence theory of truth, see Tarski (1944) and Platts (1979).

  2. Berlin (1969) clearly fits into this picture, but there is no space fully to explore the relationship of his ideas to the 1950s/1960s political science mainstream.

  3. An interpretivist approach is also endorsed, though presented less carefully and comprehensively in terms of its relationship to fundamental social-science debates, by Dworkin (1986, Chapter 2).

  4. A Weberian conception of ‘social facts’ is that they are relevant to social-scientific study only to the extent that they can be observed, for example, in surveys and election results. The concept of a ‘social fact’ is further defined, explained and developed throughout the section ‘How Searle's Thought Provide Common Ground’.

  5. It is outside the scope of the paper to discuss the speaker referent/semantic referent distinction in detail, but as a starting point see Kripke (1977).

  6. It is legitimate to apply coherentism when looking at statements internal to social reality. It is still the case that the relationship of social reality to the rest of reality, for example, brute reality, is not best explicable in coherentist terms. Belief (1) – a brute fact – for example, is not subject to revision on the grounds of a lack of consistency with beliefs (2)–(5).

  7. One could make a case that the nature of agents does become relatively more fixed when the relevant agents are humans ‘as humans’ (see Barry, 1986).

References

  • Ayer, A.J. (1946) Language, Truth and Logic, 2nd edn. London: Gollancz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Babbitt, S.E. (1997) The construction of social reality. The Philosophical Review 106 (4): 608–610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barry, C.J. (1986) Human Nature. London: Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, I. (1969) Two concepts of liberty. In: I. Berlin (ed.) Four Essays on Liberty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brecht, A. (1959) Political Theory: The Foundations of Twentieth-Century Political Thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, J.R. (1971) ‘Ought’ and institutional obligation. Philosophy 46: 309–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G.A. (2003) Facts and principles. Philosophy and Public Affairs 31 (3): 211–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1986) Law's Empire. London: Fontana Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Easton, D. (1966) The Political System: An Inquiry into the State of Political Science, 2nd edn. New York: Alfred Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, K.D. (2007) Reason's bondage: On the rationalization of sexuality. Contemporary Political Theory 6 (3): 291–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P.K. (1975) Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge. London: New Left Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnemore, M. and Sikkink, K. (1998) International norm dynamics and political change. International Organization 52 (4): 887–917.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1979) Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison, Translated by A. Sheridan. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1988–1990) The History of Sexuality, Vol. 3. Translated by R. Hurley. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Genova, A.C. (1970) Institutional facts and brute values. Ethics 81 (1): 36–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, D.J. (1991) Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The Reinvention of Nature. London: Free Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R.M. (1952) The Language of Morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H.L.A. (1997) The Concept of Law, 2nd edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, L. (2007) The Cambridge Introduction to Jacques Derrida. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hobsbawm, E.H. (1994) Age of Extremes: The Short Twentieth Century. London: Michael Joseph.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howie, G. (2006) Real essences and natural kinds in feminist theory: A revisionist account. Contemporary Political Theory 5 (3): 238–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (2000 [1739–1940]) A treatise of human nature. In: D.F. Norton and M.J. Norton (eds.) A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, A. (2005) Constructing justice for existing practice: Rawls and the status quo. Philosophy and Public Affairs 33 (3): 281–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1977) Speaker's reference and semantic reference. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 2: 255–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980) Naming and Necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S. (1962) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1985) After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory, 2nd edn. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1999) Social structures and their threats to moral agency. Philosophy 74: 311–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meckled-Garcia, S. (2008) On the very idea of cosmopolitan justice: Constructivism and international agency. Journal of Political Philosophy 16 (4) http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2007.00281.x.

  • Metz, T. (2007) The liberal case for disestablishing marriage. Contemporary Political Theory 6 (2): 196–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. (1989 [1869]) On liberty. In: S. Collini (ed.) On Liberty and Other Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheim, F.E. (1973) ‘Facts’ and ‘values’ in politics: Are they separable?. Political Theory 1 (1): 54–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Platts, M. (1979) Ways of Meaning. Boston, MA: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R. (1959) The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975) Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1: Mathematics, Matter and Method. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. (1951) Two dogmas of empiricism. The Philosophical Review 60: 20–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971) A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1980) Kantian constructivism in moral theory. The Journal of Philosophy 77 (9): 515–572.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1977) Promises and obligations. In: P.M.S. Hacker and J. Raz (eds.) Law, Morality, and Society. Oxford: Clarendon, pp. 210–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1979) Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruben, D. (1997) John Searle's the construction of social reality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (2): 443–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J.R. (1964) How to derive ‘ought’ from ‘is’. The Philosophical Review 73 (1): 43–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J.R. (1995) The Construction of Social Reality. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J.R. (2007) Freedom and Neurobiology: Reflections on Free Will, Language, and Political Power. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spragens Jr, T.A. (1973) The Dilemma of Contemporary Political Theory: Toward a Postbehavioral Science of Politics. New York: Dunellen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. (1944) The semantic conception of truth and the foundations of semantics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 4 (3): 341–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1967) Neutrality in political science. In: P. Laslett and W.G. Runciman (eds.) Philosophy, Politics, and Society, 3rd Series. New York: Barnes & Noble, pp. 25–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1971) Interpretation and the sciences of man. Review of Metaphysics 25: 3–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1982) Rationality. In: M. Hollis and S. Lukes (eds.) Rationality and Relativism. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 87–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1985a) Understanding and ethnocentricity. In: C. Taylor (ed.) Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 116–133.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1985b) What is human agency? In: C. Taylor (ed.) Human Agency and Language: Philosophical Papers 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 14–44.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. (1997) Searle on social institutions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (2): 435–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witkoski, K. (1975) The ‘is-ought’ gap: deduction of justification?. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 36 (2): 233–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zaibert, L. (2003) Intentions, promises, and obligations. In: B. Smith (ed.) John Searle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, chapter 3.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper benefited immensely from comments and criticisms provided by the following people: Saladin Meckled-Garcia, Alex Brown, Laura Valentini, Julio Montero, James McKee, Jock Gunn and two anonymous referees. This paper was presented at the PhD Workshop in Political Theory at UCL on Wednesday 16 January 2008; many thanks to all of the participants who attended this workshop.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Karp, D. Facts and values in politics and Searle's Construction of Social Reality. Contemp Polit Theory 8, 152–175 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1057/cpt.2008.28

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/cpt.2008.28

Keywords

Navigation