Skip to main content
Log in

Phenomenology and naturalism in autopoietic and radical enactivism: exploring sense-making and continuity from the top down

  • S.I.: Gestalt Phenomenology and Embodied Cognitive Science
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Radical and autopoietic enactivists disagree concerning how to understand the concept of sense-making in enactivist discourse and the extent of its distribution within the organic domain. I situate this debate within a broader conflict of commitments to naturalism on the part of radical enactivists, and to phenomenology on the part of autopoietic enactivists. I argue that autopoietic enactivists are in part responsible for the obscurity of the notion of sense-making by attributing it univocally to sentient and non-sentient beings and following Hans Jonas in maintaining a phenomenological dimension to life-mind continuity among all living beings, sentient or non-sentient. I propose following Merleau-Ponty instead, who offers a properly phenomenological notion of sense-making for which sentience is a necessary condition. Against radicalist efforts to replace sense-making with a deflationary, naturalist conception of intentionality, I discuss the role of the phenomenological notion of sense-making for understanding animal behavior and experience.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Thompson (2007), chapters 4–6. Henceforth cited as MiL.

  2. Cf. MiL 66ff. Sheredos (2017) provides a helpful clarification of Merleau-Ponty’s notion of structure, and a critique of Thompson’s appropriation of Merleau-Ponty in MiL.

  3. In fact, Thompson equates the two already at MiL 126, before introducing Jonas. But it is clear that Jonas’ line of reasoning is meant to ensure the coextension of the biological and phenomenological dimensions of the life-mind continuity thesis.

  4. Hutto and Myin (2013, 2017). Henceforth cited as RE and EE respectively.

  5. See Gallagher and Zahavi (2012, p. 201ff.) for a historical and contemporary introduction to the phenomenological approach to understanding other minds. Of course, the general validity and specific details of the phenomenological view on other minds are debated by authors working both within and without the phenomenological tradition. See, e.g., Overgaard (2017a, b).

  6. De Jesus (2016a, p. 280ff). De Jesus distinguishes between anthropomorphism, anthropocentricism, and an anthropogenic approach, but for present purposes it will suffice to focus on the issue of anthropomorphism, which I take to be the central concern here.

  7. Thompson has argued that the ability of two living bodies to resonate with one another—empathy broadly construed, in the phenomenological sense—is a precondition of any science of life and mind rather than being a threat to such science (MiL 165; Thompson 2005). It could well be argued that it is phenomenology alone, with its attention to the way in which the minds of other organism are initially given to us through their embodied activity, that can assess the nature and validity of the kinds of scientific evidence upon which a theory of non-human mindedness can be based. As Thompson also points out, a crucial task for a phenomenological cognitive science is to critique the false consciousness of the sciences of life and mind in their temptation towards a naïve objectivism (Thompson 2011, p. 118).

  8. For an excellent recent discussion of pre-predicative sense with respect to predicative and propositional sense, see Inkpin (2016).

  9. In his review of Hutto and Myin’s Evolving Enactivism (2017), Thompson (2018) also draws attention to Hutto and Myin’s neglect of this level of phenomenological description. Thompson states that, while Hutto and Myin acknowledge a basic, object-oriented intentionality, they fail to discuss the mode of presentation that characterizes such intentionality. In their defense, Hutto and Myin do grant (1) that perception is aspectual (RE 113ff.—see below), (2) that environmental offerings are given with a certain significance for the organism (RE 8), and (3) that there may be a kind of phenomenal content that is not necessarily representational content (EE 11). However, these topics are not developed in Hutto and Myin’s work sufficiently to satisfy phenomenologically-minded enactivists.

  10. As examples of “lower animals,” Merleau-Ponty discusses medusas, marine worms, starfish, and sea anemones. In a somewhat unusual classificatory move, Merleau-Ponty, following von Uexküll, includes amoebas and paramecia, both unicellular organisms, among “lower animals”.

  11. Merleau-Ponty (1963, p. 112f.; 1964a, b, p. 75; 1973, p. 104, p. 119f.; 2010, p. 6f., p. 151, pp. 209–213, p. 345, p. 430).

  12. Kiverstein and Rietveld (2015) is a notable exception to this trend. Barandiaran (2017) and Barandiaran and Moreno (2006, 2008) also conclude that the animal level of sensorimotor autonomy is the one that is relevant to the AE notion of behavior, but they arrive at this conclusion for reasons more scientific than phenomenological. Stapleton and Froese (2016) emphasize the importance of the nervous system, highlighting discontinuities in the life-mind continuity thesis where notions of subjectivity and agency are concerned. And, their strong commitment to continuity notwithstanding, both Thompson (MiL 47-49, 243ff.) and Jonas (1966, p. 99ff.; 1968, p. 244ff.) emphasize the uniqueness of the animal sensorimotor form of life.

References

  • Barandiaran, X. E. (2017). Autonomy and enactivism: Towards a theory of sensorimotor autonomous agency. Topoi, 36(3), 409–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barandiaran, X. E., & Moreno, A. (2006). On what makes certain dynamical systems cognitive: A minimally cognitive organization program. Adaptive Behavior, 14(2), 171–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barandiaran, X. E., & Moreno, A. (2008). Adaptivity: From metabolism to behavior. Adaptive Behavior, 16(5), 325–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, J. L. (2004). Why would anyone believe in god?. Walnut Creek, CA: AltaMira Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2014). The feeling body: Affective science meets the enactive mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Jesus, P. (2016a). Autopoietic enactivism, phenomenology and the deep continuity between life and mind. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 15(2), 265–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Jesus, P. (2016b). From enactive phenomenology to biosemiotic enactivism. Adaptive Behavior, 24(2), 130–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Waal, F. (2016). Are we smart enough to know how smart animals are?. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 429–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, J. (2012). Intentionality without representationalism. In D. Zahavi (Ed.), The oxford handbook of contemporary phenomenology (pp. 115–133). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (1997). Mutual enlightenment: Recent phenomenology in cognitive science. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4(3), 195–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. Forthcoming. Rethinking nature: Phenomenology and a non-reductionist cognitive science. Australasian Philosophical Review.

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2012). The phenomenological mind. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. (1969). Reduction: Ontological and linguistic facets. In M. White, S. Morgenbesser, & P. Suppes (Eds.), Philosophy, science, and method: Essays in honor of ernest nagel (pp. 179–199). New York: St Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2017). Evolving enactivism: Basic minds meet content. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Satne, G. (2015). The natural origins of content. Philosophia, 43(3), 521–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Inkpin, A. (2016). Disclosing the world: On the phenomenology of language. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1966). The phenomenon of life: Toward a philosophical biology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1968). Biological foundations of individuality. International Philosophical Quarterly, 8(2), 231–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2001). Critique of the power of judgment (trans: P. Guyer, E. Matthews). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kiverstein, J., & Rietveld, E. (2015). The primacy of skilled intentionality: On Hutto & Satne’s the natural origins of content. Philosophia, 43(3), 701–721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Köhler, W. (1927). The mentality of apes (trans: E. Winter). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

  • Maturana, H. (1980). Biology of cognition. In Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living (pp. 2–58). Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 43. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

  • Maturana, H., & Varela, F. J. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognitionthe realization of the living. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 42. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1963). The structure of behavior (trans: Alden L. Fisher). Boston: Beacon Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964a). The metaphysical in man. In Sense and non-sense (trans: H. L. Dreyfus, P. A. Dreyfus, pp. 83–98). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964b). The primacy of perception: And other essays on phenomenological psychology, the philosophy of art, history, and politics. In M. James (Ed.), Edie. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1973). The prose of the world (trans: J. O’Neil). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2003). Nature: Course notes from the Collège de France. (D. Seglard, Ed., R. Vallier, Trans). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2010). Child psychology and pedagogy: The Sorbonne lectures 19491952 (trans: T. Welsh). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Overgaard, S. (2017a). Merleau-Ponty and Wittgenstein on mindreading: Exposing the myth of the given mind. In K. Romdenh-Romluc (Ed.), Wittgenstein and Merleau-Ponty (pp. 49–65). New York: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Overgaard, S. (2017b). Other minds embodied. Continental Philosophy Review, 50(1), 65–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Romano, C. (2015). At the heart of reason (A. J. Steinbock, Ed., M. B. Smith, Trans). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Sheredos, B. (2017). Merleau-Ponty’s Immanent critique of gestalt theory. Human Studies, 40(2), 191–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spahn, C. (2016). Beyond Dualism? The implications of evolutionary theory for an anthropological determination of human being. In G. Etzelmuller & C. Tewes (Eds.), Embodiment in evolution and culture (pp. 73–96). Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stapleton, M., & Froese, T. (2016). The enactive philosophy of embodiment: From biological foundations of agency to the phenomenology of subjectivity. In Biology and subjectivity (pp. 113–29). Historical-analytical studies on nature, mind and action. Cham: Springer.

  • Thompson, E. (2005). Empathy and human experience. In J. D. Proctor (Ed.), Science, religion, and the human experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2011). Living ways of sense making. Philosophy Today, 55(Supplement), 114–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2018). Review of Review of evolving enactivism: Basic minds meet content, by Erik Myin and Daniel D. Hutto, January. https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/evolving-enactivism-basic-minds-meet-content/.

  • Thompson, E., & Stapleton, M. (2009). Making sense of sense-making: Reflections on enactive and extended mind theories. Topoi, 28, 23–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (2000). El Fénomena de La Vida. Santiago: Dolmen Essayo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991/2016). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

  • Villalobos, M., & Ward, D. (2016). Lived experience and cognitive science: Reappraising enactivism’s Jonasian Turn. Constructivist Foundations, 11(2), 204–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, A., & Varela, F. J. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(2), 97–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2017). Husserl’s legacy: Phenomenology, metaphysics, and transcendental philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to express my gratitude to Jennifer Gosetti-Ferencei, Shaun Gallagher, John Drummond, Maxime Doyon, Katsunori Miyahara, Robert Duffy, Samuel Kampa and Simon Rousseau-Lesage for comments on earlier versions of this paper. Helpful feedback was also provided by participants at the conference The World in Us: Gestalt Structure, Phenomenology and Embodied Cognition (7–9 July 2017, University of Edinburgh) and participants in Maxime Doyon’s seminar on enactivism at University of Montreal (Fall 2017). The paper benefited immensely from the thorough and insightful commentary provided by two anonymous reviewers for Synthese.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hayden Kee.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kee, H. Phenomenology and naturalism in autopoietic and radical enactivism: exploring sense-making and continuity from the top down. Synthese 198 (Suppl 9), 2323–2343 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1851-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1851-3

Keywords

Navigation