Skip to main content
Log in

Feyerabend, Pseudo-Dionysius, and the Ineffability of Reality

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper explores the influence of the fifth-century Christian Neoplatonist Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite (Denys) on the twentieth-century philosopher of science Paul Feyerabend. I argue that the later Feyerabend took from Denys a metaphysical claim—the ‘doctrine of ineffability’—intended to support epistemic pluralism. The paper has five parts. Part one introduces Denys and Feyerabend’s common epistemological concern to deny the possibility of human knowledge of ultimate reality. Part two examines Denys’ arguments for the ‘ineffability’ of God as presented in On the Divine Names. Part three then explores how Feyerabend imported Denys’ account of divine ineffability into his own metaphysics to provide a novel argument for epistemic pluralism. Part four explains the significance of an appreciation of Dionyius’ influence for our understanding of Feyerabend. I conclude that Denys was a significant and neglected influence upon the later Feyerabend.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For important recent studies, see Dear (2010), Harrison (2007) and Stark (2003).

  2. See further Kidd (2011a).

  3. Feyerabend probably first encountered Pseudo-Dionysius in Panofsky (1946). See Feyerabend (1987, 152).

  4. See further Gersh (1978) and Rorem (1993). A classic study of Christian mysticism is Turner (1995), who remarks that ‘[t]here is no field of medieval theological endeavour which Denys leaves untouched’ (216).

  5. References are to section numbers in Pseudo-Dionysius (1997).

  6. See further Janowitz (1991, 365–370).

  7. The emphasis upon the scriptural provenance of certain ‘divine names’ is necessary to preserve the authority of Christian scripture.

  8. The very idea of ‘divine names’ seems to make a positive epistemic claim—namely, that God’s attributes are plural, enumerable, and unified. Dionysius responded to this problem through complex use of prefixes: each divine name is prefixed ‘hyper-’, signifying divine unity, thus emphasising that the divine names express aspects of God up to a point, but not beyond.

  9. On the Divine Names treats the conceptual basis of human understanding of the divine, whilst its later, and sadly non-extant, sequel The Symbolic Theology, treated the perceptual basis. As Rorem puts it: ‘The Divine Names then affirmed the more numerous designations for God which come from mental concepts, while The Symbolic Theology ‘descended’ into the still more pluralized realm of sense perception and its plethora of symbols for the deity’ (Rorem, in Pseudo-Dionysius 1987, p.140fn).

  10. There are many forms of scientific realism. For a recent survey, see Devitt (2008).

  11. See Horgan (1997) and Carrier et al. (2000).

  12. For a clear account of Feyerabend’s pluralism, see Oberheim (2006).

  13. See Preston (1997) and, in response, Oberheim (2006, Ch6).

  14. Of course, Feyerabend enjoys a more radical epistemic pluralism since, unlike Pseudo-Dionysius, he had no scriptural or doctrinal commitments.

  15. As to the question of how ‘responsive’ or ‘malleable’ Being is, Feyerabend replied that ‘there is no way of finding out the limit to which the world permits [epistemic] relativism because Being itself cannot be known’ (quoted in Ben-Israel 2001, pp.97-8). The use of ‘relativism’ here is unfortunate, since ‘pluralism’ would be much wiser.

  16. Interestingly, Turner remarks that Dionysius’ work exhibits ‘little sense of a synthesis of method or outlook’ and that his aim was to ‘restore the unity … between speculative theology and … the immediacy of experience’—or, in more contemporary language, between theory and practice, just as Feyerabend aimed to do in science (1995: 126).

  17. I will shy off from giving a long list, but for some examples, see Feyerabend (1981: 21, 34, 82n4, 85–86, 139, 150–151), (1993: 266–267) and (1994). In fact, I propose that Feyerabend is engaged in ‘virtue epistemology’, but space forbids me from developing this further; see further Roberts and Wood (2007).

  18. On the relationship between theological and epistemic humility in science, see Kidd (2011b: 188–189).

  19. For a fuller account of the conception of philosophical inquiry at work here, see Kidd (2012).

  20. See further Feyerabend (2000). In an interview shortly before his death, Feyerabend remarked upon the emerging ‘religious’ or ‘spiritual’ dimensions of his later work: ‘my philosophy now has a different shape. It can’t just be that the universe just goes ‘boom!’ and develops. Is there something else? There should be!’ (quoted in Horgan 1993, p.37). Feyerabend also acknowledged that he ‘almost speak[s] as if Being is a person’ and conceded that ‘[i]t may well be—as a matter of fact I would not at all be averse to thinking of it as a kind of deus-sive-natura’ (1991, p.44).

  21. See Kidd (2011c) for some further thoughts on what this ‘doctrine of ineffability’ might be.

References

  • Ben-Israel, I. (2001). Philosophy and methodology of military intelligence: correspondence with Paul Feyerabend. Philosophia, 28, 71–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrier, M., Massey, G. J., & Reutsche, L. (Eds.). (2000). Science at century’s end: Philosophical questions on the progress and limits of science. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corrigan, K., & Harrington, L. M. (2004). Pseudo-Dionysius the areopagite. In: E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pseudo-dionysius-areopagite/.

  • Dear, P. (2010). Divine illumination, mechanical calculators, and the roots of modern reason. Science in Context, 23, 351–266.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2008). Realism/Antirealism. In S. Psillos & M. Curd (Eds.), The Routledge companion to philosophy of science (pp. 224–247). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1981). Realism, rationalism, and scientific method, philosophical papers vol. 1. Cambridge: University of Cambridge Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1987). Farewell to reason. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1991). Three dialogues on knowledge. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1993). Against method (3rd ed.). London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (2000). Letter to the reader. In Hacking 2000, 28–29.

  • Feyerabend, P. (2001). Conquest of abundance: A tale of abstraction versus the richness of being (Ed: B. Terpstra). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Feyerabend, P. (2011). The tyranny of science (Ed: E. Oberheim). Cambridge: Polity Press.

  • Gersh, S. (1978). From Iamblichus to Eriugena: An investigation of the prehistory and evolution of the Pseudo-Dionysian tradition. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (2000). Screw you, I’m going home’. Review of Feyerabend 2001, London Review of Books (22 June), 28–29.

  • Harrison, P. (2007). The fall of man and the foundations of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, J. (1993). Profile: Paul Karl Feyerabend. Science, 268(5), 36–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, J. (1997). The end of science: Facing the limits of knowledge in the twilight of the scientific age. Reading: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2000). Paul K. Feyerabend: An obituary. In J. Preston, G. Munévar, & D. Lamb (Eds.), The worst enemy of science: Essays in memory of Paul Feyerabend (pp. 3–15). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. (2002). Review of Feyerabend, Conquest of Abundance. Philosophical Investigations, 25(4), 365–370.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janowitz, N. (1991). Theories of divine names in Origen and Pseudo-Denys. History of Religions, 30(4), 359–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kidd, I. J. (2011a). Objectivity, abstraction, and the individual: the influence of Søren Kierkegaard on Paul Feyerabend. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 42, 125–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kidd, I. J. (2011b). Pierre Duhem’s epistemic aims and the intellectual virtue of humility. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 42, 185–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kidd, I. J. (2011c). Feyerabend on the ineffability of reality. In A. Kasher & J. Diller (Eds.), Models of God and other ultimate realities. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kidd, I. J. (2012). Humane philosophy and the question of progress. Ratio XXV, no. 3, forthcoming.

  • Lloyd, E. (1996). Feyerabend, Mill, and pluralism. Philosophy of Science, 64, 396–407. Supplement.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oberheim, E. (2006). Feyerabend’s philosophy. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Panofsky, E. (1946). Abbot Suger on the Abbey Church of St. Denis and its art treasures. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preston, J. (1997). Feyerabend’s retreat from relativism. Philosophy of Science, 64, 421–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pseudo-Dionysius. (1987). The complete works (Ed: P. Rorem). New York: Paulist Press.

  • Pseudo-Dionysius. (1997). Neoplatonic mysticism: Pseudo-Denys the areopagite. In K. L. Jolly (Ed.), Tradition and diversity: Christianity in a world context to 1500 (pp. 115–122). London: M.E. Sharpe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pseudo-Dionysius. (2001). Excerpt from The Mystical Theology. In C. E. Gunton, S. R. Holmes, & M. R. Rae (Eds.), The practice of theology: A reader (pp. 231–233). London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raab, C., & Haagen, H. (2007). The tradition of Catholic prayer. Minnesota: Collegeville.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, R. C., & Jay Wood, W. (2007). Intellectual virtues: An essay in regulative epistemology. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorem, P. (1993). Pseudo-Dionysius: A commentary on the texts and an introduction to their influence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stark, R. (2003). For the glory of God: How monotheism led to reformations, science, witch-hunts and the end of slavery. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, D. (1995). The darkness of God: Negativity in Christian mysticism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I offer my thanks to E.J. Lowe, Claire Graham and to the journal referees for helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ian Kidd.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kidd, I. Feyerabend, Pseudo-Dionysius, and the Ineffability of Reality. Philosophia 40, 365–377 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-011-9322-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-011-9322-9

Keywords

Navigation