Skip to main content
Log in

Breaking explanatory boundaries: flexible borders and plastic minds

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, we offer reasons to justify the explanatory credentials of dynamical modeling in the context of the metaplasticity thesis, located within a larger grouping of views known as 4E Cognition. Our focus is on showing that dynamicism is consistent with interventionism, and therefore with a difference-making account at the scale of system topologies that makes sui generis explanatory differences to the overall behavior of a cognitive system. In so doing, we provide a general overview of the interventionist approach. We then argue that recent mechanistic attempts at reducing dynamical modeling to a merely descriptive enterprise fail given that the explanatory standard in dynamical modeling can be shown to rest on interventionism. We conclude that dynamical modeling captures features of nested and developmentally plastic cognitive systems that cannot be explained by appeal to underlying mechanisms alone.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We note only to set it aside that the embedded view does not, strictly speaking, belong to this group of views given that the embedded view has been (in our view, at least) convincingly argued to be mutually exclusive to embodied, extended and enactive views (Rupert 2009). Since this is a minor issue and does not impact on the argument of this paper, we shall not comment on it any further.

  2. Note that if the metaplasticity thesis is correct, then the same holds for cognitive systems with a purely neural realisation base. For an excellent treatment of the continuous-time, complex and emergent nature of cognition – both from an extended and a neural perspective – see Malafouris (2010) and Spivey (2007).

  3. Woodward provides the following definitions of variables and values, respectively. He says: “variables are properties or magnitudes that, as the name implies, are capable of taking more than one value. Values (being red, having a mass of 1o kilograms) stand to variables (color, mass) in the relationship of determinates to determinables. Values of variables are always possessed by or instantiated in particular individuals or units, as when a particular table has a mass of 10 kg.” (2003, p. 39) One could also include to this list the particular values of a particle such as it spin ratio, momentum, polarization, and so on. Or, in systems neuroscience, for example, topological attributes of evolving graphs, time-varying aspects of global brain networks, etc.

  4. There are further conditions to be met such as the requirement that an intervention must be an ideal intervention.We leave such additional conditions aside in the rest of this paper.

  5. Clark (2017) makes this observation in the context of a different debate. We use it here because it highlights the point that we want to capture; namely, the manifold nature of systems and their boundaries.

References

  • Allen, M., & Friston, K. J. (2016). From cognitivism to autopoiesis: Towards a computational framework for the embodied mind. Synthese, 2016. https://doi.org/10.1007/s112 29-016-1288-5.

  • Ashby, R. (1960). Design for a Brain: The origins of adaptive behavior. New York: Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (1993). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as scientific research strategies. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beer, R. D. (1995). Computational and dynamical languages for autonomous agents. In R. F. Port & T. van Gelder (Eds.), Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition (pp. 121–147). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (2007). An interventionist approach to causation in psychology. In A. Gopnik & L. J. Schulz (Eds.), Causal learning: Psychology, philosophy and computation (pp. 58–66). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A., & Silberstein, M. (2008). After the philosophy of mind: Replacing scholasticism with science. Philosophy of Science, 75(1), 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2017). How to Knit Your Own Markov Blanket: Resisting the Second Law with Metamorphic Minds. Available online: http://www.x-spect.org/uploads/9/8/1/5/98154170/knittingmarkov8.pdf.

  • Craver, C. (2006). When mechanistic models explain. Synthese, 153, 355–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic Unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C., & Bechtel, W. (2007). Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biology and Philosophy, 22, 547–563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C., and Tabery, J. (2015). Mechanisms in Science. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, pp. 1–25.

  • Dupré, J. (2013). Living causes. The Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 1, 19–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K., & Stephan, K. (2007). Free-energy and the brain. Synthese, 159, 417–458.

  • Friston, K., & Frith, C. (2015). A duet for one. Consciousness and Cognition, 1–16. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2014.12.003.

  • Griffiths, P. E., & Stotz, K. (2000). How the mind grows: A developmental perspective on the biology of cognition. Synthese, 122, 29–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haken, H. (1983). Synergetics: Non-equilibrium phase transition and self-organization in physics, chemistry and biology. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgkin, A. L., & Huxley, A. F. (1952). A quantitative description of membrane current and its application to conduction and excitation in nerve. Journal of Physiology, 117, 500–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. M., & Bechtel, W. (2011). Dynamical models: An alternative or complement to mechanistic explanation. Topics in Cognitive Science, 3, 438–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. M., & Craver, C. (2011). The explanatory force of dynamical and mathematical models in neuroscience: A mechanistic perspective. Philosophy of Science, 78(4), 601–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, S. (1995). Dynamic patterns. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, M. D. (2012). Extended cognition and fixed properties: Steps to a third-wave version of extended cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11, 287–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, M. D. (2015). Extended cognition & the causal-constitutive fallacy: In search for a diachronic and dynamical conception of constitution. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90(2), 320–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, M. D. (2016). From mutual manipulation to cognitive extension: Challenges and implications. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1–16. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-016-9483-x.

  • Koschmieder, E. L. (1993). Bénard cells and Taylor vortices. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz, E. N. (1963). Deterministic nonperiodic flow. Journal of the Atmospheric Sciences, 20, 130–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L. (2004). The cognitive basis of material engagement: Where brain, body and culture conflate. In E. DeMarrais, C. Gosden, & C. Renfrew (Eds.), Rethinking Mareriality: The engagement of mind with the material world (pp. 53–62). Cambridge: McDonald Institute Monographs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L. (2010). Metaplasticity and the human becoming: Principles of neuroarchaeology. Journal of Anthropological Sciences, 88, 49–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menzies, P. (2012). The causal structure of mechanisms. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43, 796–805.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Näätänen, R., Lehtokoski, A., Lennes, M., Cheour, M., Huotilainen, M., Livonen, A., et al. (1997). Language-specific phoneme representations revealed by electric and magnetic brain responses. Nature, 385(30), 432–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palermos, O. S. (2014). Loops, constitution, and cognitive extension. Cognitive Systems Research, 27, 25–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palermos, O. S. (2016). The dynamics of group cognition. Minds and Machines, 26(4), 409–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rickles, D., Hawe, P., & Shiell, A. (2007). A simple guide to chaos and complexity. Journal of Epidemiology and Community Health, 69, 933–937.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roepstorff, A., Niewohner, J., & Beck, S. (2010). Enculturating brains through patterned practices. Neural Networks, 23, 1051–1059.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. D. (2009). Cognitive systems and the extended mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Silberstein, M., & Chemero, A. (2013). Constraints on localization and decomposition as explanatory strategies in the biological sciences. Philosophy of Science, 80, 958–970.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spivey, M. (2007). The continuity of mind. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sporns, O. (2011). Networks of the brain. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stepp, N., Chemero, A., & Turvey, M. T. (2011). Philosophy for the rest of cognitive science. Topics in Cognitive Science, 3, 425–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (2010). Exograms and interdisciplinarity: History, the extended mind, and the civilizing process. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 189–225). Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in Life. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thiese, N. D., & Kafatos, M. (2013). Complementarity in biological systems: a complexity view. Complexity, 18(6), 1–11.

  • Tronick, E. Z., Als, H., & Adamson, L. (1979). The communicative structure of face-to-face interaction. In M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before SpHEECh: The beginnings of human communication (pp. 349–372). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F., Thompson E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

  • Varga, S. (2015). Interaction and extended cognition. Synthese, 1–28. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0861-7.

  • Wolpert, D. (1996). The lack of a prior distinctions between learning algorithms. Neural Computation, 8, 1341–1390.

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2013). Mechanistic explanation: Its scope and limits. In Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 87(1), 39–65.

  • Woodward, J., & Hitchcock, C. (2003). Explanatory generalization, part 1: A counterfactual account. Nous, 37, 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Kirchhoff’s work was supported by an Australian Research Council Discovery Project “Minds in Skilled Performance” (DP170102987), a John Templeton Foundation grant “Probabilitizing Consciousness: Implications and New Directions”, and by a John Templeton Foundation Academic Cross-Training Fellowship (ID#60708). The opinions expressed in this publication are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of the John Templeton Foundation. Thanks to Lambros Malafouris for inviting us to take part in this special issue and to two anonymous reviewers for insightful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael D. Kirchhoff.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kirchhoff, M.D., Meyer, R. Breaking explanatory boundaries: flexible borders and plastic minds. Phenom Cogn Sci 18, 185–204 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9536-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9536-9

Keywords

Navigation