Skip to main content
Log in

Attention, consciousness, and the semantics of questions

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Attention influences the character of conscious perceptual experience in intricate and surprising ways, including our experience of contrast, space, and time. These patterns of influence have been argued to cause trouble for the attractive thesis that differences in the character of conscious experience flow from differences in what we represent (Block 2010). I present a novel theory of the functional role of attention that has the resources for a systematic representationalist account of these phenomena. On the erotetic theory of attention, we bring an interest to the task of perception, captured as a question we seek to answer. Questions, as understood here, are contents that cognitive systems can represent rather than sentences. We process perceptual input as a putative answer to our question in a way that is modulated by attentional focus; attentional focus aims to pick out something that matches what our question is “about.” In certain cases, this yields a form of predictive coding: if the contribution of focus matches what our question is about, we take it to select one of the possible answers we are entertaining, even though our perceptual input by itself does not supply a full answer. The proposed account also provides a new account of the phenomenology of salience.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. What I will call “representationalism” in this paper does not include a priori restrictions on what we could potentially represent in experience, e.g. objective properties in the world, properties we merely “spread onto the world,” fictional objects, sets, relations, etc.

  2. Block gives only brief consideration to a number of alternatives. If it is a high absolute degree of attention that guarantees veridicality, then, Block concludes, “if the subject were speaking on a cell phone, nothing would be veridically perceived,” since talking on a cell phone takes up some attentional resources. That “nothing” would be veridically perceived in such a case only plausibly follows if we assume that the same absolute degree of attention is required for the veridical perception of all properties. However, it could be that different properties require different degrees of attention for veridical perception. Whether the attention-drain of talking on a cell phone could impact the veridicality of our contrast representations is an empirical question; it certainly impacts the veridicality of some representations (Scholl et al. 2003). There seems to be no easy reductio ad absurdum argument against the “degrees of attention” option here. Moving on, if the distribution of attentional resources that engenders veridicality has to do with the relative deployment of attentional resources, Block holds that we run into the problem that differences between points in the visual field in terms of relative attentional resources will often be very small. Assigning a cutoff for veridicality to such small differences would be “arbitrary” (Block 2010, p. 46). However, it is not obvious why a representationalist would have to stipulate the necessary magnitude of the difference in advance. It is not obvious why this cannot be non-arbitrarily anchored in some way to what makes a difference to the percept. Another possibility Block considers is to take equal distribution of attentional resources between the two patches to yield veridical perception. He argues that we will find that there are numerous ways of assigning our attentional resources that give equal consideration to both patches, but that will still have different phenomenal character associated with them. For illustration, he suggests the example of the two patches in Fig. 5 with focus at varying points along a vertical line through the fixation point. The phenomenal character of focusing on different points on the line will be different, but the veridicality of the comparison of contrast between the patches will be the same. The idea is that this will regenerate the problem of having multiple distinct phenomenal characters that should not all be equally veridical, if they are to be cashed out in terms of different representational contents. However, Block does not provide an argument to rule out the possibility of accounting for additional differences in phenomenal character in this case in terms of differences in what is represented as more salient in the overall visual scene, while the contrast representations stay the same.

  3. One might observe that if our project is to find out something interesting and substantive to say about the nature of conscious experience, finding that extant representationalist approaches to attention are “unmotivated” is only helpful for Block’s non-representational mental paint proposal if that proposal turns out to be better motivated. As far as I can see, he provides no clear reason to think that it is. Things may be different if we regard mental paint as our null-hypothesis.

  4. Elsewhere, I argue that we can make sense of all tasks we may attentively pursue as determining questions in terms of which we can monitor performance on those tasks (Koralus 2014). However, the main points I try to make in the present paper do not depend on this broader picture.

  5. Note that in the sense at issue here, representing something as corresponding to the domain of one’s question is not trivially accomplished by just having something in one’s visual array that belongs to the domain. Suppose I have colored things in my visual array, as yet not focused on, and my question has colored objects as its domain. Does this mean I already represent something as corresponding to the domain of my question? Not in the sense intended here. Representing red somewhere in the visual array is not the same as representing something as being an element of the set of colored things. I could have the capacities to represent color properties without having the capacity to represent sets or the capacity to represent things as elements of sets.

  6. If we watch live programming, we might be interpreting the input as telling us about the actual world from a different center or perspective. If you think that the obvious flatness or slight graininess of non-3D TV images is what blocks the illusion, imagine I am addressing myself to a one-eyed audience with less than perfect visual acuity.

  7. Live performance seen at Greene Naftali Gallery, New York, 2010. The video component can be seen at http://www.bagalab.biz/work/VIdeos.html, accessed on 20 October 2012.

  8. Of course, the requisite notion of “most” here does not entail uniqueness.

  9. To avoid confusion, note that the account I propose is not that we perceive two equally sized projections on the retina and then infer that the object corresponding to one of those projections must have a different size from the other because attention made us represent it as more proximal. If the observed effects were due to an inference of this sort, they should be reversed; a nearby object has to be smaller than a more distal object, if it subtends the same degree of visual angle. The mechanism I propose is simpler and more direct and can be implemented by connections between low- or intermediate-level feature representations: A representation of proximity, activated through attention, softly activates representations of features that normally correlate with proximity (e.g., looming larger), through lateral excitatory connections that could be the result of Hebbian learning.

References

  • Adelson, E. (1993). Perceptual organization and the judgment of brightness. Science, 262, 2042–2044.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beaver, D. I., & Clark, B. Z. (2008). Sense and sensitivity: How focus determines meaning. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2010). Attention and mental paint. Philosophical Issues, 20, 23–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2009). Perceptual objectivity. Philosophical Review, 118(3), 285–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carmi, R., & Itti, L. (2005). Why do we fail to perceive jump-cuts in motion pictures? In: Proceedings of Vision Science Society Annual Meeting (VSS05).

  • Carrasco, M. (2009). Attention, cognitive models of. In P. Wilken, T. Bayne, & A. Cleeremans (Eds.), Oxford companion to consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Carrasco, M., Ling, S., & Read, S. (2004). Attention alters appearance. Nature Neuroscience, 7, 308–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrasco, M., Cigdem, P.-T., & Eckstein, M. (2000). Spatial covert attention increases contrast sensitivity across the CSF: Support for signal enhancement. Vision Research, 40, 1203–1215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2004). The representational character of experience. In B. Leiter (Ed.), The future for philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, S., & Carrasco, M. (2006). Exogenous attention and color perception: Performance and appearance of saturation and hue. Vision Research, 46(23), 4032–4047.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gobell, J., & Carrasco, M. (2005). Attention alters the appearance of spatial frequency and gap effect. Psychological Science, 16, 644–651.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, C. L. (1958). Questions. The Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 36, 159–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1990). The intrinsic quality of experience. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 31–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J., Roepstorff, A., & Friston, K. (2008). Predictive coding explains binocular rivalry: An epistemological review. Cognition, 108, 687–701.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Itti, L., & Arbib, M. A. (2006). Attention and the minimal subscene. In M. A. Arbib (Ed.), Action to language via the mirror neuron system (pp. 289–346). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Itti, L., & Baldi, P. (2005). A principled approach to detecting surprising events in video. In Proceedings in IEEE Conference on Computer Vision and Pattern Recognition (CVPR) (pp. 631–637).

  • Itti, L., & Baldi, P. (2009). Bayesian surprise attracts human attention. Vision Research, 49, 1295–1306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1890/1950). The principles of psychology (Chap. XI). New York: Dover Publications, Ch. XI.

  • Jiang, Y., Costello, P., Fang, F., Huang, M., & He, S. (2006). A gender- and sexual orientation-dependent spatial attentional effect of invisible images. PNAS, 103(45), 17048–17052.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kawabata, N. (1987). Interpretive process of depth in line drawing. Systems and Computers in Japan, 18(7), 103–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kawabata, N., & Yamagami, K. (1978). Visual fixation points and depth perception. Vision Research, 18, 853–854.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (2001). For a structured account of questions and answers. In C. Féry & W. Sternefeld (Eds.), Audiatur vox sapientiae. A Festschrift for Achim von Stechow (pp. 287–319). Berlin: Akademie-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, T., Abrams, J., & Carrasco, M. (2009). Voluntary attention enhances contrast appearance. Psychological Science, 20(3), 354–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mazza, V., Turatto, M., & Umilta, C. (2005). Foreground-background segmentation and attention: A change blindness study. Psychological Research, 69, 201–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meng, M., & Tong, F. (2004). Can attention selectively bias bistable perception? Differences between binocular rivalry and ambiguous figures. Journal of Vision, 4(7), 539–551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montagna, B., & Carrasco, M. (2006). Transient covert attention and the perceived rate of flicker. Journal of Vision, 6(9), 955–965.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1998). Conscious attitudes, attention and self-knowledge. In C. McDonald, B. Smith, & C. Wright (Eds.), Knowing our own minds: Essays on self knowledge (pp. 63–99). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, M. A., & Gibson, B. S. (1991). Directing spatial attention within an object: Altering the functional equivalence of shape descriptions. Journal of Experimental Psychology, Human Perception and Performance, 17(1), 170–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peters, R. J., & Itti, L. (2008). Congruence between model and human attention reveals unique signatures of critical visual events. Advances in Neural Information Processing Systems (Vol. 20, pp. 1145–1152). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Scholl, B. J., Noles, N. S., Pasheva, V., & Sussman R. (2003). Talking on a cellular telephone dramatically increases sustained inattentional blindness. Journal of Vision, 3:9(156a).

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2010). The contents of perception. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Accessed May 2012.

  • Spence, C., & Parise, C. (2009). Prior-entry: A review. Consciousness and Cognition, 19(1), 364–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stelmach, L. B., & Herdman, C. M. (1991). Directed attention and perception of temporal order. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 17(2), 539–550.

    Google Scholar 

  • Treisman, A., & Gelade, G. (1980). A feature integration theory of attention. Cognitive Psychology, 12, 97–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tse, P. U. (2005). Voluntary attention modulates the brightness of overlapping transparent surfaces. Vision Research, 45, 1095–1098.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolfe, J. M. (2000). Attention is fast but volition is slow. Nature, 406, 691.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, R. D., & Ward, L. M. (2008). Orienting of attention. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koralus, P. (2014) The erotetic theory of attention: Questions, focus, and distraction. Mind & Language, 29(1), 26–50.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Philipp Koralus.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Koralus, P. Attention, consciousness, and the semantics of questions. Synthese 191, 187–211 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0382-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0382-1

Keywords

Navigation