Skip to main content
Log in

A problem for achieving informed choice

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Most agree that, if all else is equal, patients should be provided with enough information about proposed medical therapies to allow them to make an informed decision about what, if anything, they wish to receive. This is the principle of informed choice; it is closely related to the notion of informed consent. Contemporary clinical trials are analysed according to classical statistics. This paper puts forward the argument that classical statistics does not provide the right sort of information for informing choice. The notion of probability used by classical statistics is complex and difficult to communicate. Therapeutic decisions are best informed by statistical approaches that assign probabilities to hypotheses about the benefits and harms of therapies. Bayesian approaches to statistical inference provide such probabilities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Two immediate questions: what constraints on an individual’s therapeutic choice are appropriate? And, when is “all else equal”? It is clear, for example, that expert advice, best evidence, and the availability of resources play a legitimate role in constraining therapeutic choice. It is also clear that everything is not equal when an individual’s rationality is in question. Then the question then becomes: what happens to the clinician’s obligation to inform choice? For a comparison of informed choice and shared decision making in the context of general practice, see [1]. For one example of a discussion on informed consent when rationality is in question, see [2].

  2. For a general discussion, see [3]; for a discussion in relation to health care, [4].

  3. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for emphasising this point. A useful example, provided by the reviewer, is of a drug that can reduce fertility. An individual wanting contraceptive cover will perceive this outcome as beneficial; an individual wanting to conceive, as an adverse effect; and an individual indifferent to the effect of the drug on fertility—for whatever reason—will be uninterested in the probability of the effect.

  4. An example of eliciting “utilities” is provided in [11]. For an example of risk communication, see [9].

  5. I put “accept” in scare quotes to acknowledge that classical statistics never fully accepts a hypothesis that has passed a test. This is in line with Popperian philosophy of science. Classical statistics provides methods for deciding when a hypothesis, usually a “null hypothesis,” can be rejected. It is when the conditions for rejection of the null hypothesis are appropriately met, that the alternative hypothesis can be provisionally “accepted.”

  6. This also assumes that the sampling distribution is monotonic, and assumes that any measurement error is small and distributed randomly.

  7. For a review of Bayesian analysis in clinical trials, see [18].

References

  1. Elwyn, G., A. Edwards, P. Kinnersley, and R. Grol. 2000. Shared decision making and the concept of equipoise: The competencies of involving patients in healthcare choices. British Journal of General Practice 50(460): 892–899.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Savulescu, J., and R.W. Momeyer. 1997. Should informed consent be based on rational beliefs? Journal of Medical Ethics 23(5): 282–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Tversky, A., and D. Kahneman. 1974. Judgement under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science 185(4157): 1124–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Epstein, R.M., B.S. Alper, and T.E. Quill. 2004. Communicating evidence for participatory decision making. Journal of American Medical Association 291(19): 2359–2366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. World Medical Association. 1964 (Last updated 2004). World Medical Association Declaration of Helsinki: Ethical principles for medical research involving human subjects. http://www.wma.net/e/policy/b3.htm. Accessed 4 June 2008.

  6. Doyal, L. 2001. Informed consent: Moral necessity or illusion? Quality in Health Care 10(supplement I): i29–i33.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Kottow, M. 2004. The battering of informed consent. Journal of Medical Ethics 30(6): 565–569.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Ford, S., T. Schofield, and T. Hope. 2003. What are the ingredients for a successful evidence based patient choice consultation? A qualitative study. Social Science & Medicine 56: 589–602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Man-Son-Hing, M., A. Laupacis, A. O’Connor, J. Biggs, E. Drake, E. Yetisir, and R. Hart. 1999. A patient decision aid regarding antithrombotic therapy for stroke prevention in atrial fibrillation: A randomised controlled trial. Journal of American Medical Association 282(8): 737–743.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Edwards, A., and G. Elwyn. 2001. Understanding risk and lessons for clinical communication about treatment preferences. Quality in Health Care 10(supplement I): i9–i13.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Col, N.F., G. Weber, A. Stiggelbout, J. Chuo, R. D’Agostino, and P. Corso. 2004. Short-term menopausal hormone therapy for symptom relief: An updated decision model. Archives of Internal Medicine 164: 1634–1640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Edwards, A., G. Elwyn, and A. Mulley. 2002. Explaining risks: Turning numerical data into meaningful pictures. British Medical Journal 324(7341): 827–830.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Ware, J.H., F. Mosteller, F. Delgado, C. Donnelly, and J.A. Ingelfinger. 1992. P values. In Medical uses of statistics, ed. John C. Bailar III and Frederick Mosteller, 181–200. Boston: NEJM Books.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Atrial Fibrillation Investigators. 1994. Risk factors for stroke and efficacy of antithrombotic therapy in atrial fibrillation. Archives of Internal Medicine 154: 1449–1457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. The SPAF III Writing Committee for the Stroke Prevention in Atrial Fibrillation Investigators. 1998. Patients with nonvalvular atrial fibrillation at low risk of stroke during treatment with aspirin. Journal of the American Medical Association 279: 1273–1277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Home, P.D., S.J. Pocock, H. Beck-Nielsen, R. Gomis, M. Hanefeld, N.P. Jones, M. Komajda, J.J.V. McMurray, and The Record Study Group. 2007. Rosiglitazone evaluated for cardiovascular outcomes—an interim analysis. New England Journal of Medicine 357(1): 28–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Drazen, J.M., S. Morrissey, and G.D. Curfman. 2007. Rosiglitazone—continued uncertainty about safety. New England Journal of Medicine 357(1): 63–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Berry, D.A. 2006. Bayesian clinical trials. Nature Reviews Drug Discovery 5(1): 27–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Poole, C. 2001. Low p-values or narrow confidence intervals: Which are more durable? Epidemiology 12(3): 291–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Young, J.M., P. Glasziou, and J.E. Ward. 2002. General practitioners’ self ratings of skills in evidence based medicine: validation study. British Medical Journal 324(7343): 950–951.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Berger, J.O., and T. Sellke. 1987. Testing a point null hypothesis: The irreconcilability of p-values and evidence. Journal of the American Statistical Association 82(397): 112–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Jason Grossman and Mark Colyvan for helpful discussion and comments on earlier drafts. I would also like to thank two anonymous referees of Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Adam La Caze.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

La Caze, A. A problem for achieving informed choice. Theor Med Bioeth 29, 255–265 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-008-9069-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-008-9069-x

Keywords

Navigation