Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-t5pn6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T18:00:37.963Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On the Interplay of the Cognitive and the Social in Scientific Practices

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

I consider the following questions, central to recent disagreements between Longino and Kitcher: Is it constitutive of making judgments of the cognitive acceptability of theories that they are made under certain social relations that embody specific social values that have been cultivated among investigators (Longino)? Or is making them (sound ones) just a consequence of social interactions that occur under these relations (Kitcher)? While generally endorsing the latter view, I make a distinction, not made by the philosophers under discussion, between sound acceptance and endorsement of a theory, and argue that Longino's view applies to endorsement.

Type
Gender and Science
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Douglas, Heather (2000), “Inductive Risk and Values in Science”, Inductive Risk and Values in Science 67:559579.Google Scholar
Haack, Susan (1997), “Science as Social?—Yes and No”, in Nelson, Lynn Hankinson and Nelson, Jack (eds.), Feminism, Science, and the Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 7993.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (1997), The Lives to Come: The Genetic Revolution and Human Possibilities. New York: Touchstone.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (2001), Science, Truth and Democracy. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (2002a), “The Third Way: Reflections on Helen Longino’s The Fate of Knowledge”, The Third Way: Reflections on Helen Longino’s The Fate of Knowledge 69:549559.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (2002b), “Reply to Helen Longino”, Reply to Helen Longino 69:569572.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (2002c) “A Case of Misrepresentation”, A Case of Misrepresentation 295: 1466.Google Scholar
Lacey, Hugh (1999), Is Science Value Free? Values and Scientific Understanding. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lacey, Hugh (2002), “Assessing the Value of Transgenic Crops”, Assessing the Value of Transgenic Crops 8:497511.Google ScholarPubMed
Lacey, Hugh (2003), “The Behavioral Scientist Qua Scientist Makes Value Judgments”, The Behavioral Scientist Qua Scientist Makes Value Judgments 31:209223.Google Scholar
Lacey, Hugh (2004), “Is There a Significant Distinction between Cognitive and Social Values?”, in Machamer, Peter and Wolters, Gereon (eds.), Science, Values and Objectivity. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press, 2451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lacey, Hugh (2005), Values and Objectivity in Science, and Current Controversy about Transgenic Crops. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Longino, Helen E. (1997), “Cognitive and Non-cognitive Values in Science: Rethinking the Dichotomy”, in Nelson, Lynn Hankinson and Nelson, Jack (eds.), Feminism, Science, and the Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 3958.Google Scholar
Longino, Helen E. (2002a), The Fate of Knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen E. (2002b), “Science and the Common Good: Thoughts on Philip Kitcher’s Science, Truth and Democracy”, Science and the Common Good: Thoughts on Philip Kitcher’s Science, Truth and Democracy 69:560568.Google Scholar
Longino, Helen E. (2002c), “Reply to Philip Kitcher”, Reply to Philip Kitcher 69:573577.Google Scholar
Machamer, Peter, and Douglas, Heather (1999), “Cognitive and Social Values”, Cognitive and Social Values 8:3641.Google Scholar
Rudner, Richard (1953), “The Scientist Qua Scientist Makes Value Judgments”, The Scientist Qua Scientist Makes Value Judgments 20:16.Google Scholar