Skip to main content
Log in

Fall and Rise of Aristotelian Metaphysics in the Philosophy of Science

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper examines the fortunes of Aristotelian metaphysics in science and the philosophy of science. It considers the Enlightenment claim that such a metaphysics is fundamentally unscientific, and that its abandonment was essential to the scientific revolution. The history of the scientific revolution and the metaphysical debates involved in it is examined, and it is argued that the eclipse of Aristotelian views was neither complete, nor merited. The evolution of Humeian and positivist accounts of science is described, and it is shown how the severe problems with these accounts, together with a revival of Aristotelian concepts in philosophy, have led to the rebirth of broadly Aristotelian accounts of the metaphysics underlying science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For defences of forms of this thesis see Zilsel (2003), Rossi (1970), Smith (2004).

  2. See Ovitt (1987), Whitney (1990), White (1978). White’s contested thesis is that Christian theology is responsible for the development of technology in Europe, a development he sees as a disaster on ecological grounds.

  3. See Duhem (1954, 1969, 1985, 1987, 1996). Duhem also wrote a number of articles for the 1912 Catholic Encyclopedia, which has helpfully been placed online at http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/index.html; they are ‘Albert of Saxony’, ‘History of Physics’, ‘Jean de Sax’, ‘Jordanus de Nemore’, ‘Nicole Oresme’, ‘Piere de Maricourt’, and ‘Thierry of Freburg’.

  4. See Burtt (1954), Koyré (1957), Lindberg (1990).

  5. For a survey see Sorabji (2005).

  6. This was because Euclidean geometry contradicted some of Epicurus’s metaphysical principles. Epicurus’s follower Polyaemus roundly asserted that ‘all of geometry is false’; see Cambiano (1999), p. 587.

  7. For discussion of the evolution of the concept and mathematics of probability, see Byrne (1968), Hacking (1975), Daston (1988), Hald (1990).

  8. Geach remarks that ‘As regards natural kinds in the animate world, Locke’s scepticism was largely based on a credulous acceptance of old wives’ tales: about rational parrots, and about “monsters” or “changelings” produced by the intercourse of bulls with mares, cats with rats, and “drills” with women’. Geach (1961), p. 88.

  9. See Koyré (1965), pp. 149–163, esp. pp. 149, 152, 149; Cohen (1987); Westfall (1986), p. 233.

  10. See Henry (1994) for discussion of alternative interpretations of Newton’s view of gravity.

  11. His view on gravity is now presented as ‘Intelligent Falling’, a satirical parody of the ‘Intelligent Design’ position of anti-Darwinists; see http://www.theonion.com/content/node/39512

  12. See Jammer (1999), pp. 40–41.

  13. See Garber (1982) on Leibniz’s early views.

  14. See Iltis (1973) for discussion of Leibniz and his followers.

  15. See Harman 1998, pp. 195–196.

  16. See Ellis 2001, pp. 263–268.

  17. See Ehring (1986) and (1997), and Dowe (2000).

  18. Suarez, for example, simply meant by ‘physical cause’ a cause that has a real influence on the production of an effect, as opposed to one that was termed a cause but did not actually produce an effect (as for example a factor that is described as a cause on the basis of its not preventing something it can and should prevent); see Suarez (1994), p. 16–17.

  19. See Aquinas (1975), ch. 69, pp. 226–235.

  20. For the new Hume, see Strawson (1989), Wright (1983); for the debate between interpretations, see Read and Richman (2000).

  21. For the move away from Kant, see Coffa (1991), Friedman (1999), and Frederick Suppe (1977), pp. 6–14.

  22. On this see Carnap (1936–1937).

  23. An important popularising description of the positivist programme is given in Ayer (1936). For a standard account of the Received View, its evolution, and objections to it, see Suppe (1977).

  24. See Stalker (1994) for discussion of Goodman’s new riddle.

  25. For the DNM see Hempel (1965).

  26. Discussed in Woodward (2003a, b).

  27. See Suppe (1977), pp. 80–86.

  28. See Feyerabend (1975) and (1987).

  29. See Lewis (1932), Marcus (1946, 1947).

  30. See Kripke (1980).

  31. See Putnam (1975).

  32. For criticism of the causal theory of reference as a basis for essentialism, see Salmon (1982) and Shapere (1984), ch. 18.

  33. See Thompson (1988) on the necessity of dispositional terms for physics.

  34. See the paper by Carnap, and criticisms of his approach, in Tuomela (1978).

  35. On the problems raised for conditional analyses of dispositions by the problems of masking and finkish dispositions, see Martin (1994), Lewis (1997), Mumford (1998) ch. 3, Bird (1998), Choi (2006); for survey and bibliography concerning dispositions generally, see Fara (2006).

  36. For these difficulties see Armstrong (1983), Tooley (1977, 1987).

  37. For this objection to laws of nature see Mumford (2004).

  38. The main examples of this approach are Popper (1935), Kuhn (1962), Lakatos (1970) and (1978), Laudan (1977).

  39. It should be mentioned that Popper introduced the Aristotelian notion of causal powers early on, in an attempt to give an account of notions of probability involved in quantum mechanics; see Popper (1957) and (1959), and Molnar (2003), pp. 105–107.

  40. See Harré and Madden (1975), Bird (2005a, b, 2006), Ellis (2001), Molnar (2003), Heil (2003), Cartwright (1983, 1989, 1999).

  41. He elaborates on this idea in Shoemaker (1984).

  42. Thus, Aquinas, in explicating Aristotle’s remarks in Physics book VIII 255b17, says that ‘to ask why a heavy thing is moved downwards is nothing other than to ask why it is heavy.’ Aquinas (1963), p. 511. This of course assumes Aristotle’s account of gravity; a Newtonian or Einsteinian account of gravity would rephrase the description of being heavy.

  43. See Ducasse (1969), p. 16.

  44. See Michotte (1946/1963), Anscombe (1981), pp. 136–137; Leslie and Keeble (1987), Fales (1990), p. 15; Sperber et al. (1995).

  45. For such defences see Molnar (2003), ch. 3; Martin and Pfeifer (1986), Place (1999a, b).

  46. See e.g. Ellis (2001), pp. 162–165.

  47. As remarked on by Woodward (2003), pp. 3–4.

  48. See van Fraassen (1980, 1989, 2002).

  49. See Dretske (1977), Tooley (1977, 1987), Armstrong (1983).

References

  • Anscombe GEM (1981) Causality and determination. In: Collected philosophical papers, vol. II. Metaphysics and the philosophy of mind, Basil Blackwell, Oxford

  • Aquinas St. T (1963) Commentary on Aristotle’s Physics (trans: Blackwell RJ, Spath RJ, Thirkell WE). Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

  • Aquinas St. T (1975) Summa contra gentiles book 3 part 1 (trans: VJ Bourke) Notre Dame University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame

  • Armstrong DM (1978) A theory of universals. CUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong DM (1983) What is a law of nature? CUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayer AJ (1936) Language, truth and logic. Victor Gollancz, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker A (2004) Simplicity, the Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2004 edn.). In: Zalta EN (ed) URL = http://www.plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2004/entries/simplicity/

  • Bird A (1998) Dispositions and antidotes. Philos Q 48:227–234

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird A (2005a) The dispositionalist conception of laws. Found Sci 10:353–370

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird A (2005b) Laws and essences. Ratio 18:437–461

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird A (2006) Potency and modality. Synthese 149:491–508

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burtt EA (1954) The metaphysical foundations of modern science. Doubleday, Garden City, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Bryne E (1968) Probability and opinion: a study of medieval presuppositions of post-medieval theories of probability. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague

    Google Scholar 

  • Cambiano G (1999) Philosophy, science, and medicine. In: The Cambridge history of Hellenistic philosophy, CUP, Cambridge

  • Carnap R (1936–1937) Testability and meaning I. Phil Sci 3:419–471. Testability and meaning II. Phil Sci 4:1–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N (1983) How the laws of physics lie. OUP, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N (1989) Nature’s capacities and their measurement. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N (1999) The dappled world: a study of the boundaries of science. CUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Choi S (2006) The simple vs. reformed conditional analysis of dispositions. Synthese 148:369–379

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coffa A (1991) The semantic tradition from Kant to Carnap: to the Vienna station. CUP, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen IB (1987) Newton’s third law and universal gravitation. J Hist Ideas 48:571–593

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daston L (1988) Classical probability in the enlightenment. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowe P (2000) Physical causation. CUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1977) Laws of nature. Phil Sci 44:248–268

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ducasse CJ (1969) Causation and types of necessity. Dover, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem P (1954) The aim and structure of physical theory (trans: Wiener P). Princeton University, Princeton

  • Duhem P (1969) To save the phenomena (trans: Doland E, Maschler C). University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Duhem P (1985) Medieval cosmology: theories of infinity, place, time, void, and the plurality of worlds. In: Ariew R (ed) (trans: Ariew R). University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Duhem P (1987) Prémices philosophiques. In: Jaki SL (ed) Brill, Leiden

  • Duhem P (1996) Essays in history and philosophy of science. In: Ariew R, Barker P (eds) (trans: Ariew R, Barker P). Hackett, Indianapolis

  • Ehring D (1986) The transference theory of causation. Synthese 67:249–258

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehring D (1997) Causation and persistence. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis B (2001) Scientific essentialism. CUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Fales E (1990) Causation and universals. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Fara M (2006) Dispositions, the Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2006 edn.). In: Zalta EN (ed) URL = http://www.plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2006/entries/dispositions/

  • Feyerabend P (1975) Against method. Verso, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend P (1987) Farewell to reason. Verso/New Left Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (1999) Reconsidering logical positivism. CUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber D (1982) Motion and metaphysics in the young Leibniz. In: Hooker M (ed) Leibniz: critical and interpretive essays. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Geach P (1961) Aquinas. In: Anscombe GEM, Geach PT. Three philosophers, Oxford, Basil Blackwell

  • Goodman N (1955) Fact, fiction, and forecast. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I (1975) The emergence of probability. University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hald A (1990) A history of probability and statistics and their applications before 1750. Wiley, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harman P (1982) The natural philosophy of James Clerk Maxwell. CUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman P (1998) Energy, force, and matter: the conceptual development of nineteenth-century physics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré R, Edward H. Madden E (1975) Causal powers. Blackwell, Oxford

  • Heil J (2003) From an ontological point of view. OUP, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel CG (1965) Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Henry J (1994) Pray do not ascribe that notion to me: God and Newton’s gravity. In: Force JE, Popkin RH (eds) The books of nature and scripture: recent essays on natural philosophy, theology and biblical criticism in the Netherlands of Spinoza’s Time and the British Isles of Newton’s Time. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1951) An enquiry concerning human understanding. In: Selby-Bigge LA (ed) 2nd edn. Oxford, Clarendon Press

  • Iltis C (1973) The Leibnizian-Newtonian debates: natural philosophy and social psychology. Br J History Sci 6:343–377

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Israel J (2001) Radical enlightenment: philosophy and the making of modernity 1650–1750. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Jammer M (1999) Einstein and religion. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Koyré A (1957) From the closed world to the infinite universe. Harper and Row, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Koyré A (1965) Gravity an essential property of matter? Newtonian Studies, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke S (1980) Naming and necessity. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass, orig. pub. 1972

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1962) The structure of scientific revolutions. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, (2nd edn. pub. 1970)

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I (1970) Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In: Lakatos I, Musgrave I (eds) Criticism and the growth of knowledge. CUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I (1978) The methodology of scientific research programmes. In: Worrall J, Currie G (ed) CUP, Cambridge

  • Laudan L (1977) Progress and its problems. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Leeuwen HG van (1963) The problem of certainty in English thought, 1630–1690. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz G (1973) Leibniz: philosophical writings. In: Parkinson GHR (ed) (trans: Morris M, Parkinson GHR). Dent, Toronto

  • Leslie J, Keeble S (1987) Do six-month-old infants perceive causality? Cognition 25:265–288

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis CI (1932) Symbolic logic (with C.H. Langford), The Appleton-Century Company, New York

  • Lewis D (1997) Finkish dispositions. Philos Q 47:143–158

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindberg DC (1990) Conceptions of the scientific revolution from bacon to butterfield: a preliminary sketch. In: Reappraisals of the scientific revolution, CUP, Cambridge

  • Locke J (1975) An essay concerning human understanding. In: Nidditch P (ed) Oxford, Clarendon Press

  • Marcus RB (1946) A functional calculus of first order based on strict implication. J Symbol Logic 11:1–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marcus RB (1947) The Identity of Individuals in a Strict Functional Calculus of Second Order. J Symbol Logic 12:1–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin CB (1994) Dispositions and conditionals. Philos Q 44:1–8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin CB, Pfeifer K (1986) Intentionality and the non-psychological. Philos Phenomenol Res 46:531–554

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michotte AE (1946/1963) The perception of causality. Basic books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill JS (1973) A system of logic ratiocinative and inductive, in Collected works of John Stuart Mill, vol. VIII, University of Toronto Press, Toronto

  • Molnar G (2003) Powers: a study in metaphysics. In: Mumford S (ed) OUP, Oxford

  • Mumford S (1998) Dispositions. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford S (2004) Laws in nature. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Nadler S (1988) Cartesianism and Port-Royal. The Monist 71:573–584

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton I (1725) Mathematical principles of natural philosophy, 3rd edn. (trans: Motte A, rev. Cajori F, 1952), Encyclopedia Britannica, Chicago

  • Newton I (1782) Opera. In: Horsley S (ed) vol. IV, London

  • Newton I (1952) Optics. Encyclopedia Britannica, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Ovitt G (1987) The restoration of perfection: labor and technology in medieval culture. Rutgers University Press, New Brunswick

    Google Scholar 

  • Place UT (1996) Intentionality as the mark of the dispositional. Dialectica 50:99–120

    Google Scholar 

  • Place UT (1999) Intentionality and the physical: a reply to Mumford. Philos Q 49:225–231

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper K (1935) Logik der Forschung, Vienna, Julius Springer Verlag, (trans: as The Logic of Scientific Discovery, 1959), Hutchinson, London

  • Popper K (1957) The propensity interpretation of the calculus of probability, and the quantum theory. In: Körner S (ed) Observation and interpretation in the philosophy of physics. Dover, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K (1959) The propensity interpretation of probability. Br J Philos Sci 10:25–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H (1975) The meaning of “Meaning”. In: Mind, language and reality: philosophical papers, vol. 2, CUP, Cambridge

  • Quine, W.V.O.: 1961, ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’, In: From a logical point of view, 2nd rev. edn. Harvard University Press, Harvard

  • Read R, Richman KA (eds) (2000) The new Hume debate, Routledge, London

  • Rossi P (1970) Philosophy, technology, and the arts in the early modern era (trans: Attanasio S), Harper & Row, New York

  • Salmon NU (1982) Reference and essence. Basil Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapere D (1984) Reason and the search for knowledge. Reidel, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker S (1980) Properties and inductive projectability. In: Cohen LJ, Hesse M (eds) Applications of inductive logic. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker S (1984) Identity, cause & mind: philosophical essays. CUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith PH (2004) The body of the artisan: art and experience in the scientific revolution. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorabji R (2005) The philosophy of the commentators. 200–600 A.D.: volume 2: physics. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber D, Premack D, Premack A (1995) Causal cognition. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalker D (ed) (1994) Grue!: the New Riddle of induction, Open Court, Chicago

  • Strawson G (1989) The secret connexion: causation, realism, and David Hume. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Suarez F (1994) On efficient causality: metaphysical disputations 17, 18, and 19 (trans: Freddoso AJ), Yale University Press, New Haven

  • Suppe F (1977) The search for philosophic understanding of scientific theories. In: Suppe F (ed) The structure of scientific theories 2nd edn. University of Illinois Press, Urbana

    Google Scholar 

  • Sylla ED (1991) The Oxford calculators and the mathematics of motion 1320–1350. Harvard Dissertations in the History of Science, New York & London

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson IJ (1988) Real dispositions in the physical world. Br J Philos Sci 39(1):67–79

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley M (1977) The nature of laws. Can J Phil 7:667–698

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooley M (1987) Causation: a realist approach. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela R (ed) (1978) Dispositions, D. Reidel, Dordrecht

  • Van Fraassen B (1980) The scientific image, Oxford University Press

  • Van Fraassen B (1989) Laws and symmetry. OUP, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen B (2002) The Empirical stance. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Westfall RS (1986) The rise of science and the decline of orthodox Christianity: a study of Kepler, Descartes, and Newton. In: Lindberg DC, Numbers RL (eds) God and nature: historical essays on the encounter between Christianity and science. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Whiston W (1708) A new theory of the earth, 2nd edn. London

  • White L (1978) Medieval religion and technology: collected essays. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitney E (1990) Paradise restored: the mechanical arts from antiquity through the thirteenth century, vol. 80. Transactions of the American Philosophical Society, Philadelphia

  • Whyte L (1961) Roger Joseph Boscovich. Fordham University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2003a) Scientific explanation, the Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2003 edn.). In: Zalta EN (ed) URL = http://www.plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2003/entries/scientific-explanation/

  • Woodward J (2003b) Making things happen. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright JP (1983) The sceptical realism of David Hume. Manchester University Press, Manchester

    Google Scholar 

  • Zilsel E (2003) The social origins of modern science. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Lamont.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Lamont, J. Fall and Rise of Aristotelian Metaphysics in the Philosophy of Science. Sci & Educ 18, 861–884 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-007-9118-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-007-9118-2

Keywords

Navigation