Skip to main content
Log in

The Four-Case Argument and the Existential/Universal Effect

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

One debate surrounding Derk Pereboom’s (2001, 2014) four-case argument against compatibilism focuses on whether, and why, we judge manipulated agents to be neither free nor morally responsible. In this paper, we propose a novel explanation. The four-case argument features cases where an agent is the only individual in her universe who has been manipulated. Let us call manipulation whose scope includes at least one but not all agents existential manipulation. Contrast this with universal manipulation, which affects all agents within a universe. We propose that we find agents in Pereboom’s manipulation cases less free and morally responsible in part because they are the target of existential manipulation. We empirically tested this hypothesis and found that people’s free will and moral responsibility judgments were sensitive to the scope of manipulation: people judged existentially manipulated agents significantly less free and responsible than universally manipulated agents.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Though we focus on Pereboom’s four-case argument in this paper, our findings will likely generalise to other manipulation arguments against compatibilism (see Kane 1996; Mele 2006) as well.

  2. One could also defend a weaker hypothesis: we find Plum less responsible because his decision has been determined by factors beyond his control. Todd (2011) argues this is all Pereboom needs for the four-case argument to go through. We will consider this weak version of the determinism hypothesis, and the competing hypotheses, when discussing their predictions.

  3. McKenna (2008) calls this strategy the ‘soft-line,’ In contrast, McKenna’s (2008) hard-liners argue that agents in manipulation cases really are free and responsible. For hard-line responses, see Fischer (2011), McKenna (2008, 2014), and Sartorio (2016).

  4. This response has some empirical support. See Feltz (2013), Murray & Lombrozo (2017), and Phillips & Shaw (2015). However, Björnsson (in prep) found that non-agential manipulation (by infection) undermined attributions of free will and responsibility to the same degree agential manipulation did. For empirical work that explores other effects on free will and responsibility intuitions, see, for example, Björnsson (2014), Nahmias et al. (2005, 2006), Nichols & Knobe (2007), Rose & Nichols (2013), and Roskies & Nichols (2008).

  5. McKenna has also recently noted the existential nature of Pereboom’s manipulation cases: “We are not invited to suppose that all agents in the world inhabited by Plum (in Case 1 or Case 2) are so manipulated, nor are we to make any further assumptions that at Plum’s world (in Case 1 or Case 2) determinism is true” (2017: 583).

  6. We also tested a closely related hypothesis regarding existential and universal determinism. We predicted that participants would find an agent who is the only individual in the universe whose behaviour is causally determined to be less free and responsible than an agent who exists in a universe in which everyone’s behaviour is causally determined.

  7. The manipulation vignettes are modelled on Pereboom’s (2001, 2014) Case 3 and Feltz’s (2013) culture vignette, though we describe manipulation in terms of agents’ upbringing, instead of community training, to make the scenarios more accessible. One might argue that the manipulator’s presence is not robust enough in our scenarios to test the manipulator hypothesis. However, we think describing Katie as being “raised since birth to make decisions that almost always benefit her” is relevantly similar to describing her as being “extensively trained by [her] community to make decisions that almost always benefit [her]” (Feltz 2013: 56). Furthermore, even if these scenarios do not sufficiently highlight the intentional actions of other agents, our research still counts against the manipulator hypothesis, which predicts no existential/universal effect.

  8. Strictly speaking existential determinism may not be nomologically possible, but you can grasp this idea by imagining a backwards light-cone behind each agent, such that the specific facts in that backward light-cone in conjunction with the laws of nature causally determine some agents’ actions but not others (see Ismael 2016).

  9. Rerunning our analyses, our reported results are not impacted by including statement order as a factor.

  10. One might worry that the descriptions of manipulation and determinism in the vignettes are compatible with these factors influencing (or failing to influence) agents’ actions as opposed to determining (or failing to determine) them. However, our comprehension checks asked whether Katie/most people’s actions are completely determined by their upbringing/past facts and laws of nature, so we were able to rule out participants who formed mere-influence judgments. Still, it would be good for future studies to test different wordings to confirm the present results.

  11. We also found a significant main effect of moral responsibility/free will F(1,269) = 30.212, p < .001, and significant two-way interaction between moral responsibility/free will and existential/universal F(1, 269) = 11.307, p = .001. We discuss these effects in the concluding section.

  12. Not all defenders of the manipulator hypothesis would accept this prediction. Some defenders of this hypothesis argue that manipulation mitigates free will and moral responsibility when a manipulator intends that an agent perform a particular action and then intervenes to ensure that they do so (e.g., Deery & Nahmias 2017; Waller 2014). Since our manipulation vignettes, like Pereboom’s Case 3 and Feltz’s culture case, do not state that those who raised Katie intended to ensure that she would kill Plum, these theorists would likely not defend the claim that Katie is less free and responsible in our manipulation conditions, just as they resist the claim that Plum is less free and responsible in Pereboom’s Case 3 (Deery & Nahmias 2017: 1268, footnote 12). Thus, the fact that there was no difference between participants’ judgments in the manipulation and determinism conditions does not threaten these approaches to the manipulator hypothesis. However, the fact that there was a significant difference between participants’ judgments in the existential and universal conditions indicates that these views are incomplete, for these views make no mention of the role existential and universal forms of manipulation play in affecting our judgments of free will and moral responsibility. We hope to more directly explore the ways in which intention and scope of manipulation affect judgements of free will and moral responsibility in future research. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for encouraging us to explore these approaches to the manipulator hypothesis.

  13. Björnsson & Pereboom (2016) levy this criticism against Feltz (2013) and Murray & Lombrozo (2017).

  14. Simple effects tests with Bonferroni correction were conducted on the two-way interaction between moral responsibility/free will judgment and existential/universal condition. For existential vignettes, moral responsibility judgments (M = 5.19, SD = 1.38) were significantly higher than free will judgments (M = 4.47, SD = 1.51; p < .001). However, for universal vignettes, we observed no significant difference between moral responsibility (M = 5.76, SD = 1.38) and free will judgments (M = 5.58, SD = 1.51; p = .124). Crucially, both moral responsibility (p = .001) and free will judgments (p < .001) were significantly higher in universal vignettes than existential vignettes.

  15. But this is not to say that there is no principled difference between existential and universal cases. In (Latham & Tierney forthcoming), we explore how our responsibility practices are impacted in very different ways by universal and existential phenomena. We then argue that this is a principled difference, especially on Strawsonian approaches to moral responsibility, which take facts about our responsibility practices to be deeply connected to the nature of responsibility itself. This research can also be utilised to support accounts that take free will to be a natural kind. Anthony Flew (1955) first suggested that the meaning of the term ‘free will’ was fixed by ordinary paradigm cases, and several philosophers have recently argued that the meaning of free will depends on what paradigm cases of free will have in common (Deery 2019; Heller 1996; Latham 2019). But as Peter Van Inwagen (1983) points out, these views are consistent with it turning out that we are free even when we are all being manipulated by Martians, which he takes to be absurd. However, our research indicates that this is not an absurd implication. Participants typically take ‘free will’ to successfully refer in cases where manipulation and/or determinism is the norm, and they are less likely to take ‘free will’ to refer in cases where manipulation and/or determinism were not features of the paradigm.

References

  • Björnsson, Gunnar. (in prep). Manipulators, parasites, and generalization arguments.

  • Björnsson, G. (2014). Incompatibilism and “Bypassed” agency. In A. R. Mele (Ed.), Surrounding free will (pp. 95–112). Oxford University Press.

  • Björnsson, G., & Pereboom, D. (2016). Traditional and experimental approaches to free will. In W. Buckwalter & J. Sytsma (Eds.), Companion to experimental philosophy (pp. 142–157). Blackwell.

  • Deery, O. (2019). Free actions as a natural kind. Synthese, 198(1), 823–843.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deery, O., & Nahmias, E. (2017). Defeating manipulation arguments: Interventionist causation and compatibilist sourcehood. Philosophical Studies, 174(5), 1255–1276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, A. (2013). Pereboom and premises: Asking the right questions in the experimental philosophy of free will. Consciousness and Cognition, 22(1), 53–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (2011). The zygote argument remixed. Analysis, 71, 267–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heller, M. (1996). The mad scientist meets the robot cats: compatibilism, kinds, and counterexamples. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 56(2), 333–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ismael, J. (2016). How physics makes us free. Oxford University Press.

  • Kane, R. (1996). The significance of free will. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Latham, A. J. (2019). The conceptual impossibility of free will error theory. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 15(2), 99–120.

  • Latham, A. J., & Tierney, H. (forthcoming). Defusing existential and universal threats to compatibilism. Journal of Philosophy.

  • McKenna, M. (2008). A hard-line reply to Pereboom’s four-case manipulation argument. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 77(1), 142–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2014). Resisting the manipulation argument: A hard-liner takes it on the chin. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 89(2), 464–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2017). Manipulation arguments, basic desert, and moral responsibility: Assessing Derk Pereboom’s free will, agency, and meaning in life. Criminal Law and Philosophy, 11, 575–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2006). Free will and luck. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Murray, D., & Lombrozo, T. (2017). Effects of manipulation on attributions of causation, free will, and moral responsibility. Cognitive Science, 4, 447–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E., Morris, S., Nadelhoffer, T., & Turner, J. (2005). Surveying freedom: Folk intuitions about free will and moral responsibility. Philosophical Psychology, 18, 561–584.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E., Morris, S., Nadelhoffer, T., & Turner, J. (2006). Is incompatibilism intuitive? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 73(1), 28–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Knobe, J. (2007). Moral responsibility and determinism: The cognitive science of folk intuitions. Noûs, 41, 663–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without free will. Cambridge University Press.

  • Pereboom, D. (2014). Free will, agency, and meaning in life. Oxford University Press.

  • Phillips, J., & Shaw, A. (2015). Manipulating morality: Third-party intentions alter moral judgments by changing causal reasoning. Cognitive Science, 39, 1320–1347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rose, D., & Nichols, S. (2013). The lesson of bypassing. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4(4), 599–619.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roskies, A., & Nichols, S. (2008). Bringing moral responsibility down to earth. The Journal of Philosophy, 105, 371–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartorio, C. (2016). Causation and free will. Oxford University Press.

  • Schlosser, M. (2015). Manipulation and the zygote argument: Another reply. Journal of Ethics, 19(1), 73–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todd, P. (2011). A new approach to manipulation arguments. Philosophical Studies, 152(1), 127–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1983). An Essay on Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press

  • Waller, R. R. (2014). The threat of effective intentions to moral responsibility in the zygote argument. Philosophia, 42, 209–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank two anonymous referees, Michael Mckenna, Shaun Nichols, Eddy Nahmias, Kristie Miller and the Metaphysics Reading Group at the University of Sydney for their helpful comments on earlier versions of the manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrew J. Latham.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Latham, A.J., Tierney, H. The Four-Case Argument and the Existential/Universal Effect. Erkenn 88, 2379–2389 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-021-00458-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-021-00458-x

Keywords

Navigation