Skip to main content
Log in

Perception of Free Will: The Perspective of Incarcerated Adolescent and Adult Offenders

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

    We’re sorry, something doesn't seem to be working properly.

    Please try refreshing the page. If that doesn't work, please contact support so we can address the problem.

Abstract

The existence of free will has been both an enduring presumption of Western culture and a subject for debate across disciplines for millennia. However, little empirical evidence exists to support the almost unquestioned assumption that, in general, Westerners endorse the existence of free will. The few studies that measure belief in free will have methodological problems that likely resulted in underestimating the true extent of belief. Recently, Rakos et al. (Behavior and Social Issues 17:20–39, 2008) found a stronger endorsement of free will when demand characteristics were eliminated. The current study builds on this work by sampling incarcerated adolescents and adults, whose freedom to act is externally constrained. Belief in free will as well as attitudes toward punishment, self-esteem, and locus of control were measured. The results indicate that free will is strongly endorsed in Western society even when freedom to act is severely restricted. However, incarcerated adolescents endorsed free will to a slightly lesser extent than their nonincarcerated counterparts from Rakos et al. (Behavior and Social Issues 17:20–39, 2008), while incarcerated and nonincarcerated adults offered equally strong endorsements. The comparable endorsement by adults is consistent with the hypothesis that the belief in agency is an evolutionary adaptation. The small decrease found for incarcerated adolescents may reflect the interaction between developmental factors and the expression of an evolutionary adaptation. Additionally, incarcerated adolescents and adults associated beliefs in free will with viewing punishment as a means of deterrence, rehabilitation, and retribution. Incarcerated adults, but not incarcerated adolescents, associated beliefs in free will with greater self-esteem and with an external locus of control. Finally, though both incarcerated adults and adolescents endorsed free will strongly, the former manifested the belief by emphasizing free agentic choice whereas the latter focused on the personal responsibility that is interwoven with free choice. The implications of these findings are discussed in the context of evolutionary, cultural, and developmental factors.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Neuroscience research suggests that conscious awareness of an intention to act follows physiological initiation of a voluntary response by approximately 500 milliseconds (e.g., Banks and Isham 2009; Libet et al. 1983; Rigoni et al. 2011).

  2. Examples: “You choose what you do—your neurons don’t just fire at will;” “Even though you have neural impulses, your free will allows you to look over those impulses and decide for yourself;” “I can choose what I want to do;” “We have many impulses but we all have the power to go against them;” “Neural impulses are part of our will” (pp. 218, 220).

  3. Examples: “it makes us sound like robots; “It goes against my own personal beliefs” (p.217).

  4. Examples: “Neural impulses all have to begin somewhere;” “Neural impulses are caused due to our free will” (p. 217).

  5. Psychologically, compatibilists contend that humans can direct some behavior independent of immediate external events through processes such as cognitive self-regulation (e.g., Bandura 2008). Philosophically, compatibilism emphasizes moral responsibility for conscious choice rather than the factors that might constitute the ultimate source of that choice (see McKenna 2009, for discussion). Holmstrom’s (1977) compatibilism suggests that free will is present when a person, first, has and wants to fulfill a particular desire and, second, has actual control over the sources of the desire so control over action is achieved, a position similar to Bandura’s.

  6. Recent research suggests the belief in free will is associated with less cheating, reduced aggression, and greater helpfulness (Baumeister et al. 2009; Vohs and Schooler 2008)

  7. Indirect support for this hypothesis is provided by Rigoni et al. (2011), who found that weakened beliefs in free will suppressed physiological motor preparation. This suppression occurred more than one second prior to the conscious decision to act, possibly decreasing the amount of intentional effort put into action.

  8. These alternative models lead to differing perceptions of choice. Indians reported a sense of free choice when expected to help another, but Americans reported a sense of being compelled (Miller 2003) and U.S. college students perceive making more choices in their daily lives than college students from India; however, the Indian students perceive proportionally more of their choices to occur within an interpersonal rather than individualistic context (Savani et al. 2010).

  9. Even though adolescents and adults endorsed the belief in free will to the same extent, it is possible that the belief in adolescents, who are still maturing,’ is less stable than the belief in adults.

  10. This inverse relationship might reflect an important component of the psychological compatibilist viewpoint—the more one endorses internal libertarian-like agency, the more one is also aware of external constraints on choice and therefore on the operation of that agency.

  11. Beyond incapacitation of the offender, which physically protects society, punishment can also serve as a general deterrent to future unlawful acts through observational learning processes, as a mechanism through which to rehabilitate the offender via therapy, education, job training, etc., and finally, as retribution that establishes moral legitimacy by giving the offender his or her “just deserts” (i.e., the severity of the consequence is proportionate to the offending act) (Bartol and Bartol 1994).

  12. These data were collected as part of a larger study.

  13. The “Social and Personal Attitudes Scale” can be found in Rakos et al. (2008), available at www.bfsr.org.

  14. One reviewer of this paper argued that the items in this scale measured free will in the compatibilist rather than libertarian sense, because most of the items do not eliminate determinism as a consideration; therefore a subject can assert that people have moral responsibility for their actions and are in charge of their decisions and yet believe that their actions and decisions are externally determined. However, the data in the Nahmias et al. studies and the Monroe and Malle study reviewed earlier suggest that people do not in actuality adopt this stance.

  15. The extent of belief in free will of nonincarcerated adults [M = 87.70] and adolescents [M = 88.08] in the Rakos et al. (2008) study also did not differ from each other [t(178) = .28, p = n.s.].

  16. We did not employ a confirmatory factor analysis because our sample was too small. Hair et al. (1998) recommends a 10:1 ratio of observations to variables; we had 192 subjects and 22 variables.

References

  • Baer, J., J.C. Kaufman, and R.F. Baumeister (eds.). 2008. Are we free? Psychology and free will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bandura, A. 1989. Human agency in social cognitive theory. American Psychologist 44: 1175–1184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bandura, A. 2006. Toward a psychology of human agency. Perspectives on Psychological Science 1: 164–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bandura, A. 2008. Reconstrual of “free will” from the agentic perspective of social cognitive theory. In Are we free? Psychology and free will, ed. Baer, Kaufman, and Baumeister, 86–123. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Banks, W.P., and E.A. Isham. 2009. We infer rather than perceive the moment we decide to act. Psychological Science 20: 17–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartol, C.R., and A.M. Bartol. 1994. Psychology and law: Research and application, 2nd ed. Pacific Grove: Brooks/Cole.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister, R.F. 2008. Free will, consciousness, and cultural animals. In Are we free? Psychology and free will, ed. Baer, Kaufman, and Baumeister, 65–85. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister, R.F., E.J. Masicampo, and C.N. DeWall. 2009. Prosocial benefits of feeling free: Disbelief in free will increases aggressions and reduces helpfulness. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 35: 260–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F.H.C. 1994. The astonishing hypothesis. New York: Scriber’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D.C. 2003. Freedom evolves. New York: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dilman, I. 1999. Free will: An historical and philosophical introduction. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erikson, E.H. 1956. The problem of ego identity. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association 4: 56–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleming, J.S., and B.E. Courtney. 1984. The dimensionality of self-esteem. II. Hierarchical facet model for revised measurement scales. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 39: 921–929.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P., and M. Tsakiris. 2009. The experience of agency: Feelings, judgments, and responsibility. Current Directions in Psychological Science 18(242): 246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hair, J.F., R.E. Anderson, R.L. Tatham, and W.C. Black. 1998. Multivariate data analysis, 5th ed. Upper Saddle River: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haynes, S.D., D. Rojas, and W. Viney. 2003. Free will, determinism, and punishment. Psychological Reports 93: 1013–1021.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heine, S.J., D.R. Lehman, H.R. Markus, and S. Kitayama. 1999. Is there a universal need for positive self-regard? Psychological Review 106: 766–794.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holstrom, N. 1977. Firming up soft determinism. The Personalist 58: 39–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Juth, N., and F. Lorentzon. 2010. The concept of free will and forensic psychiatry. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 33: 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R.H. (ed.). 2002. The Oxford handbook of free will. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, J. 2005. In genes we trust: The biological component of psychological essentialism and its relationship to mechanisms of motivated social cognition. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 85: 686–702.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B., C.A. Gleason, E.W. Wright, and D.K. Pearl. 1983. Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness-potential): The unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act. Brain 106: 623–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B., A. Freeman, and K. Sutherland (eds.). 1999. The volitional brain: Toward a neuroscience of free will. Exeter: Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Markus, H.R., and S. Kitayama. 2003. Models of agency: Sociocultural diversity in the construction of action. In Cross-cultural differences in perspectives of the self, ed. V. Murphy-Berman and J. Berman, 1–57. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. 2009. Compatibiism. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Retrieved from: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/compatibilism/ [January 13, 2011].

  • Menon, U., and R.A. Shweder. 1998. The return of the “white man’s burden”: The moral discourse of anthropology and the domestic life of Hindu women. In Welcome to middle age! (And other cultural fictions), ed. R.A. Shweder, 139–188. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, J.G. 2003. Culture and agency: Implications for psychological theories of motivation and social development. In Cross-cultural differences in perspectives of the self, ed. V. Murphy-Berman and J. Berman, 60–99. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monroe, A.E., and B.F. Malle. 2010. From uncaused will to conscious choice: The need to study, not speculate about people’s folk concept of free will. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1: 211–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E., S. Morris, T. Nadelhoffer, and J. Turner. 2004. The phenomenology of free will. Journal of Consciousness Studies 11(7–8): 162–179.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E., S. Morris, T. Nadelhoffer, and J. Turner. 2005. Surveying freedom: Folk intuitions about free will and moral responsibility. Philosophical Psychology 18: 561–584.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias, E., D.J. Coates, and T. Kvaran. 2007. Free will, moral responsibility, and mechanism: Experiments on folk intuitions. Midwest Studies in Philosophy XXXI: 214–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nettler, G. 1959. Cruelty, dignity, and determinism. American Sociological Review 24: 375–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. 2008. How can psychology contribute to the free will debate? In Are we free? Psychology and free will, ed. Baer, Kaufman, and Baumeister, 10–31. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, T. 2010. Free will. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Retrieved from: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/freewill/ [January 13, 2011].

  • Rakos, R.F. 2004. The belief in free will as a biological adaptation: Thinking inside and outside the behavior analytic box. European Journal of Behavior Analysis 5: 95–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rakos, R.F., K.R. Laurene, S. Skala, and S. Slane. 2008. Pervasiveness and correlates of belief in free will. Behavior and Social Issues 17: 20–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reynolds, W.M. 1988. Measurement of academic self-concept in college students. Journal of Personality Assessment 52: 223–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rigoni, D., S. Kuhn, G. Sartori, and M. Brass. 2011. Inducing disbelief in free will alters brain correlates of preconscious motor preparation: The brain minds whether we believe in free will or not. Psychological Science 22: 613–618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, J.P., and P.R. Shaver. 1973. Measures of social psychological attitudes. Ann Arbor: Institute for Social Research.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, J.P., P.R. Shaver, and L.S. Wrightsman (eds.). 1991. Measures of personality and social psychological attitudes (Vol. 1). San Diego: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, M. 1965. Society and the adolescent self-image. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rotter, J.B. 1966. Generalized expectancies for internal versus external control of reinforcement. Psychological Monographs, 80 (1, Whole No. 609).

  • Rotter, J.B. 1990. Internal versus external control of reinforcement: A case history of a variable. American Psychologist 45: 489–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkissian, H., A. Chatterjess, F. De Brigard, J. Knobe, S. Nichols, and S. Sirker. 2010. Is belief in free will a cultural universal? Mind & Language 25: 346–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savani, K., H.R. Markus, N.V.R. Naidu, S. Kumar, and N. Berlia. 2010. What counts as choice? U.S. Americans are more likely than Indians to construe action as choice. Psychological Science 21: 391–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savin-Williams, R.C., and G.A. Jaquish. 1981. The assessment of adolescent self-esteem: A comparison of methods. Journal of Personality 49: 324–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, D.P., and J.J. Pilcher. 2004. Evaluating evidence of psychological adaptation: How do we know when we see one? Psychological Science 15: 643–649.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, J.M., and S. Begley. 2002. The mind & the brain: Neuroplasticity and the power of mental force. New York: Harper Perennial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sie, M., and A. Wouters. 2010. The BCN challenge to compatibilist free will and personal responsibility. Neuroethics 3: 121–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B.F. 1971. Beyond freedom and dignity. New York: Bantam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stroessner, S.J., and C.W. Green. 2001. Effects of belief in free will or determinism on attitudes toward punishment and locus of control. Journal of Social Psychology 130: 789–799.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valecha, G. K. 1972. Construct validation of internal-external locus of control as measured by an abbreviated 11-item IE scale. Unpublished doctoral dissertation. The Ohio State University, 1972.

  • Valecha, G.K., and T.M. Ostrom. 1974. An abbreviated measure of internal-external locus of control. Journal of Personality Assessment 38: 369–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viney, W., P. Parker-Martin, and S.D.H. Dotten. 1988. Beliefs in free will and determinism and lack of relation to punishment rationale and magnitude. The Journal of General Psychology 115: 15–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viney, W., D.A. Waldman, and J. Barchilon. 1982. Attitudes toward punishment in relation to beliefs in free will and determinism. Human Relations 35: 939–950.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vohs, K.D., and J.W. Schooler. 2008. The value of believing in free will: Encouraging a belief in determinism increases cheating. Psychological Science 19: 49–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldman, D.A., W. Viney, P.A. Bell, J.B. Bennett, and S. Hess. 1983. Internal and external locus of control in relation to beliefs in free will and determinism. Psychological Reports 53: 631–634.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D.M. 2002. The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D.M. 2008. Self is magic. In Are we free? Psychology and free will, ed. Baer, Kaufman, and Baumeister, 226–247. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kimberly R. Laurene.

Additional information

While all authors agree that the belief in free will exists and is an important topic of study, there is variability among them regarding the actual existence of free will.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Laurene, K.R., Rakos, R.F., Tisak, M.S. et al. Perception of Free Will: The Perspective of Incarcerated Adolescent and Adult Offenders. Rev.Phil.Psych. 2, 723–740 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-011-0074-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-011-0074-z

Keywords

Navigation