Skip to main content
Log in

A theory of meaning

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A theory of word meaning developed jointly by Adrienne and Keith Lehrer is summarized, which accommodates the empirical facts of natural languages, especially the diversity of types of words. Reference characterizes the application of words to things, events, properties, etc. and sense the relationship among words and linguistic expressions. Although reference and sense are closely connected, neither can be reduced to the other. We use the metaphor of vectors to show how different, sometimes competing forces interact to provide an understanding of what a word in context means. Topics discussed include vagueness, indeterminacy, the role of experts, possible worlds, pragmatic influences, semantic change, semantic networks, fields, and entailments. A formal theory for understanding the relationship of idiolects, dialects, and communal languages is proposed to account for the dynamic interaction of individuals and communities which occurs continuously.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Austin, J. L. (1963). How to do things with words. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K., & Harnish, R. M. (1979). Language, communication, and speech acts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (1984). Coherence, consensus, and language. Linguistics and Philosophy, 5, 483–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K., & Lehrer, A. (1998). Semantic fields and vectors of meaning. In B. Lewandowska-Tomaszczyk (Ed.), Lexical semantics, cognition, and philosophy (pp. 123–137). Lódz: Lódz University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K., & Wagner, C. (1980). Rational consensus in science and society. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, J. (1963). Structural semantics. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, J. (1977). Structural semantics 1: Semantic fields. In his Semantics, Vol 1 (pp. 230–317). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mercier, A. (1992). Linguistic competence, convention, and authority: Individualism and anti-individualism in linguistics and philosophy. Unpublished PhD dissertation, UCLA, Los Angeles, CA.

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of meaning. Language, mind, knowledge. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 7, 131–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1951). Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review, 60, 20–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1969). Speech acts. London, NewYork: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vendler, Z. (1967). Verbs and times. In Z. Vendler (Ed.), Linguistics in philosophy (pp. 97–121). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1968). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ziff, P. (1972). Understanding understanding. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Adrienne Lehrer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Lehrer, A. A theory of meaning. Philos Stud 161, 97–107 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9934-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9934-3

Keywords:

Navigation