Skip to main content
Log in

No purely epistemic theory can account for the naturalness of kinds

  • S.I.: Natural Kinds: Language, Science, and Metaphysics
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Several philosophers have recently tried to define natural kinds in epistemic terms only. Given the persistent problems with finding a successful metaphysical theory, these philosophers argue that we would do better to describe natural kinds solely in terms of their epistemic usefulness, such as their role in supporting inductive inferences. In this paper, I argue against these epistemology-only theories of natural kinds and in favor of, at least partly, metaphysical theories. I do so in three steps. In the first section of the paper, I propose two desiderata for a theory of natural kinds. In the second section, I discuss one example of a ‘general’ epistemology-only theory, proposed by Marc Ereshefsky and Thomas Reydon, and argue that theories like theirs fail to provide adequate criteria of natural kinds. In the third section, I focus on one example of a ‘specific’ epistemology-only theory, proposed by P. D. Magnus, and use it to show why such theories cannot justify the claim that the proposed epistemic criteria account for the naturalness of kinds.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Most philosophers implicitly accept this monism about natural kinds, for some examples consider the criteria of Wilkerson (1988) and Ellis (2001).

  2. For doubts about the notion of mind-independence by an essentialist, see Wilkerson (1988). For a broader discussion of the troubles with spelling out naturalness in terms of mind-independence, by a non-essentialist, see Khalidi (2016).

  3. There is some debate in the literature on whether Boyd holds the view that all natural kinds are HPC’s. In my view, this just depends on how broadly one defines the notion of an HPC, that is, whether it also includes kinds that do have necessary and sufficient conditions for kind-membership. In any case, nothing important depends on this for the purposes of this paper.

  4. In this paper I will only discuss realist epistemic theories of natural kinds. There are some other epistemic theories of natural kinds that are explicit about not conceiving of ‘naturalness’ as a realist notion anymore (Franklin-Hall 2015). These theories abandon the idea that the naturalness of kinds lies somehow in getting something right about the world – which conventional categories do not – but rather conceive of the ‘naturalness’ of a category as a particular role this category can have in a scientific theory or discipline. McLeod (2010) defends a theory like this, according to which natural kinds allow for many generalizations (criterion), explaining their unitary role for scientific fields (naturalness). If having a unitary role for science is not understood as a ‘sign’ of naturalness anymore, but as naturalness itself, I don’t see why we should still call this naturalness. Hence in this paper I only discuss those epistemic theories that explicitly aim to provide a realist but epistemic answer to the problem of natural kinds.

  5. What is described here is one method for species delimitation based on the PPSC. This is not to say, however, that different (ontological) species concepts will always result in incompatible (or even different) ways of delimiting species. See Wiens (2007).

  6. In fact, their criteria seem to originate from an earlier text of Ereshefsky where he asks exactly this question (Ereshefsky 2001). Also telling for the fact that the proposed criteria are an awkward fit for a theory of natural kinds, is that Ereshefsky himself elsewhere calls the phylo-phenetic species concept ‘nominalistic’ (Ereshefsky 2010).

  7. For the details on this restriction clause, see Magnus (2012).

  8. Practical success here is meant to refer to that type of success that is not reducible to epistemic success. Thus, one particular isotope could perhaps be a natural kind for chemists or physicists based on epistemic success. Furthermore, it could also be a natural kind for economists based on epistemic considerations. However, the fact that it is practically useful as a currency is the result of it being sufficiently rare and stable, and hence not due to its epistemic credentials. One cannot think of this isotope as a natural kind simply based on the fact that it is sufficiently rare and stable. Practical success in this non-epistemic sense does not make for natural kinds.

References

  • Bird, A., & Tobin, E. (2016). “Natural Kinds”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/natural-kinds/.

  • Boyd, R. (1980). Scientific realism and naturalistic epistemology. In PSA: Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. Chicago: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 613–662.

  • Boyd, R. (1988). How to be a moral realist. In G. Sayre-McCord (Ed.), Essays on moral realism (pp. 181–228). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1991). Realism, anti-foundationalism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philosophical Studies, 61, 127–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1999a). Kinds, complexity and multiple realization. Philosophical Studies, 95, 67–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1999b). Homeostasis, species and higher taxa. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays (pp. 141–186). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (2000). Kinds as the “workmanship of men”: Realism, constructivism, and natural kinds. In J. Nida-Rümelin (Ed.), Rationalität, Realismus, Revision: Vorträge des 3. Internationalen Kongresses der Gesellschaft für Analytische Philosophie (pp. 52–89). Berlin: De Gruyter.

  • Brigandt, I. (2009). Natural kinds in evolution and systematics: Metaphysical and epistemological considerations. Acta Biotheoretica, 57, 77–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coenye, T., Gevers, D., Peer, Y. V., Vandamme, P., & Swings, J. (2005). Towards a prokaryotic genomic taxonomy. FEMS Microbiology Reviews, 29(2), 147–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohan, F. M. (2002). What are bacterial species? Annual Reviews in Microbiology, 56(1), 457–487.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collier, J. (1996). On the necessity of natural kinds. In Peter Riggs (Ed.), Natural kinds, laws of nature and scientific methodology (pp. 1–10). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2009). Mechanisms and natural kinds. Philosophical Psychology, 22(5), 575–594.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. (1983). Kripke and Putnam on natural kind forms. In C. Ginet & S. Shoemaker (Eds.), Knowledge and mind (pp. 84–101). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (2002). Is ‘Natural Kind’ a natural kind term? The Monist, 85(1), 29–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dykhuizen, D. E., & Green, L. (1991). Recombination in Escherichia coli and the definition of biological species. Journal of Bacteriology, 173(22), 7257–7268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2001). The poverty of the Linnaean hierarchy: A philosophical study of biological taxonomy. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2010). Microbiology and the species problem. Biology and Philosophy, 25(4), 553–568.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M., & Reydon, T. A. (2015). Scientific kinds. Philosophical Studies, 172, 969–986.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin-Hall, L. R. (2015). Natural kinds as categorical bottlenecks. Philosophical Studies, 172(4), 925–948.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (1999). Squaring the Circle: Natural Kinds with Historical Essences. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays (pp. 209–228). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Häggqvist, S. (2005). Kinds, projectibility and explanation. Croatian Journal of Philosophy, 13, 71–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation. New York, NY: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kendig, C. (Ed.). (2016). Natural kinds and classification in scientific practice. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalidi, M. A. (2013). Natural categories and human kinds. Classification in the natural and social sciences. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalidi, M. A. (2016). Mind-dependent kinds. Journal of Social Ontology, 2(2), 223–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (1993). Inductive inference and its natural ground: An essay in naturalistic epistemology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. A. (1972). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1987). Progress or Rationality? The prospects for normative naturalism. American Philosophical Quarterly, 24, 19–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1990). Normative naturalism. Philosophy of Science, 57, 44–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemeire, O. (2014). Soortgelijke stoornissen. Over nut en validiteit van classificatie in de psychiatrie, 76(2), 217–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemeire, O. (2016). Beyond the realism debate: the metaphysics of ‘racial’ distinctions. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 59, 47–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2008). Essentialism, metaphysical realism, and the errors of conceptualism. Philosophia Scientiae, 12(1), 9–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, P. D. (2011). Drakes, seadevils, and similarity fetishism. Biology and Philosophy, 26(6), 857–870.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, P. D. (2012). Scientific enquiry and natural kinds: From planets to mallards. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, P. D. (2014). NK ≠ HPC. The Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 471–477.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, P. D. (2018). Taxonomy, ontology, and natural kinds. Synthese, 195(4), 1427–1439.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLeod, M. (2010). The epistemology-only approach to natural kinds. In F. Stadler (Ed.), The epistemology-only approach to natural kinds. A reply to Thomas Reydon (Vol. 1). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1843). A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive: Being a connected view of the principles of evidence, and the methods of scientific investigation (Vol. 2). London: JW Parker.

    Google Scholar 

  • Platts, M. (1983). Explanatory kinds. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 34(2), 133–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). Mind, language, and reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Regier, D. A., Narrow, W. E., Clarke, D. E., Kraemer, H. C., Kuramoto, S. J., Kuhl, E. A., et al. (2013). DSM-5 field trials in the United States and Canada, part II: test-retest reliability of selected categorical diagnoses. American Journal of Psychiatry, 170, 59–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosselló-Mora, R., & Amann, R. (2001). The species concept for prokaryotes. FEMS Microbiology Reviews, 25, 39–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stackebrandt, E. (2006). Defining taxonomic ranks. In S. Falkow, E. Rosenberg, K. H. Schleifer, E. Stackebrandt, M. Dworkin (Eds.), The prokaryotes. Springer, New York, pp. 29–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2008). Depth: An account of scientific explanation. Harvard University Press.

  • Tahko, T. E. (2015). Natural kind essentialism revisited. Mind, 124(495), 795–822.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiens, J. J. (2007). Species delimitation: new approaches for discovering diversity. Systematic Biology, 56(6), 875–878.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkerson, T. E. (1988). Natural kinds. Philosophy, 63, 19–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A., Barker, M. J., & Brigandt, I. (2007). When traditional essentialism fails: Biological natural kinds. Philosophical Topics, 35, 189–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zachar, P. (2002). The practical kinds model as a pragmatist theory of classification. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 9(3), 219–227.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhi, X. Y., Zhao, W., Li, W. J., & Zhao, G. P. (2012). Prokaryotic systematics in the genomics era. Antonie van Leeuwenhoek, 101(1), 21–34.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

Fonds voor Wetenschappelijk Onderzoek—Vlaanderen. Postdoctoral fellowship.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Olivier Lemeire.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lemeire, O. No purely epistemic theory can account for the naturalness of kinds. Synthese 198 (Suppl 12), 2907–2925 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1806-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1806-8

Keywords

Navigation