Searle on the biology of seeing

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2018.10.004Get rights and content

Highlights

  • Biologism is distinguished from Narrow Biologism.

  • One can accept Biologism without accepting Narrow Biologism.

  • Searle's main arguments for his views on seeing depend on an untenable Narrow Biologism.

Abstract

Searle offers an account of seeing as a conscious state not constituted by the object(s) seen. I focus in this article on his biological case for this thesis, and argue that the biological considerations he adduces neither establish his own position nor defeat a rival object-inclusive view. I show (among other things) that taking seeing to be a biological state is compatible with its being (partially) constituted by the object(s) seen.

Introduction

Over many decades, John Searle has championed a version of a view we may call “Biologism”—the thesis that, insofar as humans and other conscious animals are concerned, anything mental (including any conscious state) is biological.1 An important recent work of his proves to be no exception.2 Therein, he argues that all conscious states are biological and as such are realized in cellular systems and caused by biological processes. As he puts it:

Consciousness with all of its touchy-feely, “mysterious,” ontologically subjective features is a biological, and therefore physical, part of the world. As such, it enters into causal relations with other parts of the physical world. Thus, for example, all of my conscious perceptions are caused in my brain by the impact of perceptual stimuli on my nervous system. And these perceptions in turn together with other processes, some conscious and some unconscious, cause my physical behavior. For example, I see the glass of beer in front of me, so I reach out with my hand, take it, and drink from it. Some people still think that the ontological irreducibility of consciousness makes consciousness not a part of the physical world. They are mistaken (…) [T]he very conscious state which is qualitative, subjective, touchy-feely, etc. must have a lower-level description in which it is a biological process causing the secretion of acetylcholine. This is no more mysterious than the fact that my car engine has a higher-level description where the explosions in the cylinder move the piston, and a lower-level description where the oxidation of hydrocarbon molecules releases heat energy (48–49).

A particular concern of Searle's is to offer an account of seeing as a conscious state, and a significant part of his case for this account appeals to biological considerations. I focus in this article on this biological case.3 I argue that, even if we accept Biologism, the biological considerations Searle adduces neither establish his own position nor defeat a rival object-inclusive view: ultimately, his appeals to biology do not settle the question of the ontology of seeing.

This article unfolds as follows. In the next five sections, I address some preliminary matters useful for assessing Searle's case: I delineate what I call the “Intra-Organismic Conditional” in section 2, distinguish between Biologism and a species of it I dub “Narrow Biologism” in section 3, delineate some key assumptions of the article in section 4, discuss the state of depression as a prelude to seeing in section 5, and distinguish between the object-exclusive and object-inclusive conceptions of seeing in section 6. After these preliminaries, I summarize Searle's account of seeing in section 7, and then present his biological case and show why it fails to establish his own position and to defeat the rival object-inclusive view in section 8. I consider, in terms of its implications for seeing, an argument Searle deems to be decisive against consciousness existing outside the brain in section 9, I conclude with some retrospective and prospective remarks in section 10.

Section snippets

The intra-organismic conditional

Biology, as the scientific study of life, is a many-splendored thing. It encompasses both intra-organismic and extra-organismic branches: the former focus on what goes on within living organisms, and the latter focus on the interactions of living organisms with other organisms and the world around them. A paradigmatic example of an intra-organismic branch is neurobiology, the study of nervous systems. A paradigmatic example of an extra-organismic branch is ecology, the study of the interactions

Biologism and narrow biologism

As noted above, Biologism is the thesis that, insofar as humans and other conscious animals are concerned, anything mental (including any conscious state) is biological.7 This thesis may be stated as follows:

  • (iii)

    For any x, if x is mental, then x is biological.

We may distinguish a species of Biologism we may dub “Narrow Biologism” according to which, insofar as humans and other conscious animals are concerned, anything mental

Three key assumptions

In light of the points above and for the sake of argument in the ensuing discussion, I shall make the following three key assumptions. (1) Biologism (as distinguished above from Narrow Biologism) is true. (2) Seeing objects does not require a logically prior awareness of something else (such as a sense-datum or idea) mediating between the seer and seen objects. (3) Seen objects exist independently of being seen. I make these assumptions, not because I think they are so obvious as to not be

Depression as prelude to seeing

In order to understand and assess Searle's account of seeing, it's helpful for the sake of comparison to attend first to another kind of mental state such as the state of depression.

Being depressed can presumably be caused by an outside event. Suppose for instance that Jill breaks up with Bill, thereby causing him to fall into a state of depression. No doubt Jill's breaking up with him causes intermediate events in Bill's brain and central nervous system that culminate in his being depressed.

Object-inclusive and object-exclusive conceptions of seeing

Now consider Jill's seeing Bill. I do not mean her dating him, but rather her seeing him in the primary sense of the verb—e.g., (say) Bill enters the room, and Jill sees (visually perceives) him. Suppose with Searle that we think of Jill's seeing Bill as a conscious state of hers.12 Given this supposition, and assuming Biologism,

Searle's account of seeing summarized

Searle offers a version of the object-exclusive conception of seeing. On it, whether Jill sees Bill or hallucinates him, in both cases she has a conscious visual experience as of Bill. This visual experience is a putative common kind of which Jill's seeing Bill and her hallucinating him are each species. When Jill sees Bill, her visual experience is caused by light quanta reflected from his body that impinge on her visual system causing neural events that eventuate in this experience; when she

Searle's biological arguments for the object-exclusive conception

We have seen above what Searle's object-exclusive conception of seeing amounts to. We turn now to his biological case for it.

Searle adduces a number of biological considerations in favor of his view, and they may be helpfully collected and reconstructed as three main arguments. We may call them the Argument from Intentionality, the Argument from Consciousness, and the Argument from Causal Efficacy. If sound, these arguments would not only establish his version of the object-exclusive conception

Searle's “decisive” argument

In the previous section, we saw how Searle offered in effect three main arguments putatively predicated on biological considerations for his object-exclusive conception of seeing. Each argument, were it sound, would imply that the object-inclusive conception of seeing is incorrect. Because of its implications for how to think of seeing as a conscious state, it is also worth considering an argument Searle deems decisive against consciousness existing outside the brain:

The decisive argument

Conclusion

To his credit, Searle rightly emphasizes the importance of biology in understanding consciousness more generally, and a conscious state such as seeing more particularly. But howevcr much we may find Biologism plausible and even appealing, we have seen above that assuming it does not by itself favor an object-exclusive conception of seeing like Searle's over the alternative object-inclusive conception. None of the biological considerations that Searle adduces dictates that we must choose one

Acknowledgments

I am very grateful to Katherine Le Morvan, Rick Kamber, and to reviewers of this journal for very helpful comments.

References (19)

  • William Alston

    Back to the theory of appearing

    Philosophical Perspectives

    (1999)
  • Jonathan Balcombe

    What a fish knows: The inner lives of our underwater cousins

    (2016)
  • Bill Brewer

    Perception and its objects

    (2011)
  • John Campbell

    Reference and consciousness

    (2002)
  • Neil A. Campbell et al.

    Biology: Concepts and connections

    (2003)
  • Fred Dretske

    Seeing and knowing

    (1969)
  • William Fish

    Perception, hallucination, and illusion

    (2013)
  • James Gibson

    The ecological approach to perception

    (1986)
  • Pierre Le Morvan

    Intentionality: Transparent, translucent, and opaque

    Journal of Philosophical Research

    (2008)
There are more references available in the full text version of this article.

Cited by (0)

View full text