Skip to main content
Log in

The Applicability of Mathematics as a Philosophical Problem: Mathematization as Exploration

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper discerns two types of mathematization, a foundational and an explorative one. The foundational perspective is well-established, but we argue that the explorative type is essential when approaching the problem of applicability and how it influences our conception of mathematics. The first part of the paper argues that a philosophical transformation made explorative mathematization possible. This transformation took place in early modernity when sense acquired partial independence from reference. The second part of the paper discusses a series of examples from the history of mathematics that highlight the complementary nature of the foundational and exploratory types of mathematization.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The systematic connections between conceptions of logic and axiomatics have been investigated in Lenhard and Otte (2010).

References

  • Antonelli, A., & May, R. C. (2000). Frege’s new science. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 41(3), 242–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bachelard, G. (1938). La formation de l’esprit scientifique. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bangu, S. (2012). The applicability of mathematics in science: Indispensability and ontology. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P. (1965). What numbers could not be. Philosophical Review, 74, 47–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley, G. (1901). Alciphron, or the minute philosopher. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley, G. (1989). Philosophical works. London: Everyman’s Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boutroux, P. (1920). L’Ideal scientifique des mathematiciens. Paris: Alcan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, R. E., & Sandifer, C. E. (2009). Cauchy’s cours d’analyse algebrique (An Annotated Translation). NY: Springer.

  • Cassirer, E. (1953). Substance and function (originally 1910 in German). New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer, E. (1969). The problem of knowledge: Philosophy, science, and history since hegel (5th ed.). New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic structures. The Hague: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Toledo Piza, A. (2003). Heisenberg and Schrödinger. Sao Paulo: Odysseus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dedekind, R. (1963). Essays on the theory of numbers. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dirac, P. (1966). Lectures on quantum mechanics. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engel, F. (Ed.) (1894). Hermann Grassmanns gesammelte mathematische und physikalische Werke. Leipzig: Teubner.

  • Euler, L. (1748/1983). Einleitung in die Analysis des Unendlichen (Introductio in Analysin Infinitorum) (Vol. I.). Heidelberg: Springer.

  • Foucault, M. (1973). The order of things. New York, NY: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1884). The foundation of arithmetic. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1892). On sense and reference. In P. Geach, & M. Black (Eds.), Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 56–78. Cited according to Moore, G. W. (1993), Meaning and Reference, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Frege, G. (1956). The thought: A logical inquiry. Mind, 65(259), 289–311. (Original publication “Der Gedanke: Eine logische Untersuchung”, in: Beiträge zur Philosophie des Deutschen Idealismus, I, 58–77, 1918).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1980). Philosophical and mathematical correspondence. In G. Gabriel, & McGuinness (Eds.), Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

  • Frege, G. (1986). Logische Untersuchungen. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck+Ruprecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galileo, G. (1954). Dialogues concerning two new sciences. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P., & Black, M. (1970). Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heijenoort, Jv. (1967). Logic as calculus and logic as language. Synthese, 17, 324–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heisenberg, W. (1971a). Physics and beyond: Encounters and conversations. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heisenberg, W. (1971b). Schritte über Grenzen. München: Piper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heisenberg, W. (1974). Across the frontiers. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hersh, R. (1997). What is mathematics really?. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1997). Lingua Universalis vs. calculus ratiocinator, Selected Papers (Vol. 2). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Jesseph, D. J. (1993). Berkeley’s philosophy of mathematics. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1787). Critique of pure reason (“B” refers to pagination of second edition from 1787), P. Guyer (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1998.

  • Katz, J. (2004). Sense, reference, and philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, J. (1968). Greek mathematical thought and the origin of algebra. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. W. (1989). Meditations on knowledge, truth, and ideas (1684). In Ariew, R., & Garber, D. (Eds.), Philosophical essays (pp. 23–27). Hackett Publishing Company, Indianapolis.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lenhard, J., & Carrier, M. (Eds.) (2017). Mathematics as a tool. Tracing new roles of mathematics in the sciences. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science 327, New York: Springer.

  • Lenhard, J., & Otte, M. (2010). Two types of mathematization. In B. Van Kerkhove, J. De Vuyst, & J. P. Van Bendegem (Eds.), Philosophical perspectives on mathematical practice (pp. 301–330). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1975). An essay concerning human understanding. Edited with an introduction, critical apparatus and glossary by Peter H. Nidditch, Oxford: Clarendon.

  • McGinn, C. (2000). Logical properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N. J. (1999). Model-based reasoning in conceptual change. In L. Magnani, N. J. Nersessian, & P. Thagard (Eds.), Model-based reasoning in scientific discovery (pp. 5–22). New York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, Ch. S., Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volumes I–VI, ed. by Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiß, Cambridge, Mass. (Harvard UP) 1931–1935, Volumes VII-VIII, ed. by Arthur W. Burks, Cambridge, Mass. (Harvard UP) 1958 (quoted by no. of volume and paragraph).

  • Pincock, C. (2012). Mathematics and scientific representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1951). The rise of scientific philosophy. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, J. R. (2007). A metaphysics for the mob: The philosophy of George Berkeley. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1956). Introduction to mathematical philosophy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schüling, H. (1969). Die Geschichte der axiomatischen Methode im 16. und beginnenden 17. Jahrhundert. Hildesheim: Olms-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seboek, Th. (1990). Indexicality. The American Journal for Semiotics, 7, 7–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, M. (1998). The applicability of mathematics as a philosophical problem. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waismann, F. (1970). Einführung in das mathematische Denken (3rd ed., originally published 1936). München: DTV.

  • Weinberg, St. (2017). The trouble with quantum mechanics. The New York Review of Books, LXIV(1), 51–53.

  • Winkler, K. (1994). Berkeley. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Johannes Lenhard.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lenhard, J., Otte, M. The Applicability of Mathematics as a Philosophical Problem: Mathematization as Exploration. Found Sci 23, 719–737 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-018-9546-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-018-9546-2

Keywords

Navigation