Skip to main content
Log in

Performing abstraction: two ways of modelling Arabidopsis thaliana

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

What is the best way to analyse abstraction in scientific modelling? I propose to focus on abstracting as an epistemic activity, which is achieved in different ways and for different purposes depending on the actual circumstances of modelling and the features of the models in question. This is in contrast to a more conventional use of the term ‘abstract’ as an attribute of models, which I characterise as black-boxing the ways in which abstraction is performed and to which epistemological advantage. I exemplify my claims through a detailed reconstruction of the practices involved in creating two types of models of the flowering plant Arabidopsis thaliana, currently the best-known model organism in plant biology. This leads me to distinguish between two types of abstraction processes: the ‘material abstracting’ required in the production of Arabidopsis specimens and the ‘intellectual abstracting’ characterising the elaboration of visual models of Arabidopsis genomics. Reflecting on the differences between these types of abstracting helps to pin down the epistemic skills and research commitments used by researchers to produce each model, thus clarifying how models are handled by researchers and with which epistemological implications.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8
Fig. 9

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See the collections of essays edited by Morgan and Morrison (1999), de Chadarevian and Hopwood (2004) and Laubichler and Muller (2007) for examples of how different types of models are combined in scientific research. Note that it is not within the scope of this paper to provide an innovative definition of what a ‘model’ is: the broadly defined notion of models as mediators, put forward by Morgan and Morrison (1999), suffices for my purposes.

  2. Griesemer (2004, p. 436).

  3. This estimate is based on data collected by The Arabidopsis Information Resource in 2006.

  4. The history of research on Arabidopsis and its progressive institutionalisation (including the establishment of the Multinational Arabidopsis Steering Committee) is documented in Somerville and Koornneef (2002), Meyerowitz (2001), Meinke et al. (1998) and Leonelli (2007).

  5. I visited The Arabidopsis Information Centre in August 2004 and the Nottingham Arabidopsis Stock Centre in May 2005. At both centres, Directors Sue Rhee and Sean May provided me with access to their archives and resources. I also had the possibility to interview them and their staff at length, thus gathering information about how they construct and use the models.

  6. Another two sites are the Munich Information Centre for Protein Sequences [MIPS] and the ‘Arabidopsis.info’ based at the Nottingham Arabidopsis Stock Centre [NASC].

  7. The initial focus on genomics was determined by the abundance of data gathered through the Arabidopsis Genome Initiative (the multinational project that successfully sequenced the plant’s genome between 1996 and 2000). TAIR personnel insists that the choice to organise the database on the basis of genomic data is pragmatic rather than conceptual, and that the ultimate TAIR aim is to obtain balance and integration of information pertaining to the genomic, the evolutionary and the ecological levels (pers. comm.). Nevertheless, as I show, the commitment to emphasise gene-level data prevents TAIR from giving equal space to data concerning higher levels of organisation in Arabidopsis.

  8. A model of metabolic cycle is displayed in Fig. 5. See TAIR website for further examples.

  9. More information on this project can be found online: http://obo.sourceforge.net/

  10. The definitions used for the concepts employed in GO are agreed upon during GO Content Meetings, in which developers discuss their choices with experts in relevant biological domains.

  11. Note that ‘schema’ in TAIR terminology does not denote the organisation of data into various categories (which occurs in steps 1–3), but rather the way in which programmers visualise these categories through available digital technologies.

  12. My list is not supposed to be exhaustive, but rather to give an idea of the confusion underlying the use of the term ‘abstract’ in discussions of modelling practices.

  13. See Cat (2001) for an exploration of this notion of abstraction in relation to Maxwell’s work.

  14. A good exemplification of this view can be found in Cartwright (1999): a description is abstract insofar as it can be ‘fitted out’ to a number of other descriptions. Similarly, the characterisation of a model as abstract or concrete depends on the context in which the model is used. This approach is captured by Radder’s definition of abstraction as ‘summarising’, which he identifies (and goes on to criticise) as one of three main senses in which abstraction works (2006: 110).

  15. The use of intellectually abstracted models is increasingly widespread among biologists. Take the pervasive use of simulations and algorithms to visualise empirical data, not to mention the push towards formalisation and away from the laboratory brought about by the increasing use of bioinformatics to store, organise and integrate data. These models are especially useful for elaborating explanations or confirming predictions stemming from given hypotheses (what Cartwright calls interpretative models in her 1999, p. 181). They are also fundamental to the integration of biological knowledge concerning specific phenomena (as, for instance, bringing together insights from physiology, genomics and cell biology to understand root development in plants). However, precisely because of their strict reliance on theoretical assumptions, models constructed through intellectual abstracting are not very helpful in cases where the goal of their manipulation is to improve the empirical content of a theory. They give little indication as to which features of the phenomenon under scrutiny should be considered relevant to the development of explanatory knowledge about that phenomenon. Further, such models do not help with testing the empirical (descriptive) accuracy of the relation it stipulates between theoretical terms and aspects of the phenomenon.

  16. See Clarke and Fujimura (1992).

References

  • Bard JBL, Rhee S (2004) Ontologies in biology: design, applications and future challenges. Nat Rev Genet 5:213–222

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowker GC, Star SL (1999) Sorting things out. Classification and its consequences. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N (1983) How the laws of physics lie. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N (1999) The dappled world. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Cat. J (2001) On understanding: Maxwell on the methods of illustration and scientific metaphor. Stud Hist Philos Mod Phys 32(3):395–441

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Chadarevian S, Hopwood N (2004) Models. The third dimension of science. Stanford University Press, Stanford, California

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke AE, Fujimura JH (1992) The right tools for the job. At work in twentieth-century life sciences. Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey

    Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer JR (2004) Three-dimensional models in philosophical perspective. In: de Chadarevian, Hopwood N (eds) Models. The third dimension of science. Stanford University Press, Stanford, California, pp 433–442

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I (1970) Methodology of scientific research programmes. In: Lakatos I, Musgrave A (eds) Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, pp 91–196

    Google Scholar 

  • Laubichler M, Müller GB (2007) Modeling biology. Structures, behaviours, evolution. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Leonelli S (2007) Arabidopsis, the botanical Drosophila: from mouse cress to model organism. Endeavour 31(1):34–38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meinke DW et al. (1998) Arabidopsis thaliana: a model plant for genome analysis. Science 282:662–682

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meinke D, Scholl R (2003) The preservation of plant genetic resources. Experiences with Arabidopsis. Plant Physiol 133:1046–1050

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meyerowitz EM (2001) Prehistory and history of Arabidopsis research. Plant Physiol 125:15–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan MS, Morrison M (1999) Models as mediators. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi M (1962) Personal knowledge. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Polanyi M (1967) The tacit dimension. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Radder H (2006) The world observed/the world conceived. Pittsburgh University Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Somerville C, Koornneef M (2002) A fortunate choice: the history of Arabidopsis as a model plant. Nat Rev Genet 3:883–889

    Article  Google Scholar 

Internet resources

Download references

Acknowledgments

Discussions with Rachel Ankeny, Hasok Chang, James Griesemer, Henk de Regt and Hans Radder were crucial to the development of my analysis. Thomas Reydon, Rasmus Winther, an anonymous reviewer and the editor closely read and commented upon the last draft, which has considerably improved as a result. I also thank the Arabidopsis researchers who shared their time, facilities and thoughts with me: Sue Rhee and her team at the TAIR and Sean May and his team at the NASC. This research was supported by the Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research (NWO), The Leverhulme Trust and the ESRC.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sabina Leonelli.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Leonelli, S. Performing abstraction: two ways of modelling Arabidopsis thaliana . Biol Philos 23, 509–528 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-007-9081-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-007-9081-y

Keywords

Navigation