Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-gtxcr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-23T05:29:45.589Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Incarnation: divine embodiment and the divided mind

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 June 2011

Robin Le Poidevin
Affiliation:
University of Leeds

Extract

The central doctrine of traditional Christianity, the doctrine of the Incarnation, is that the Second Person of the Trinity lived a human existence on Earth as Jesus Christ for a finite period. In the words of the Nicene Creed, the Son is him

who for us men, and for our salvation, came down from heaven, and was incarnate by the Holy Ghost of the Virgin Mary, and was made man.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Stevenson, J., Creeds, Councils and Controversies: Documents illustrating the early history of the church 373–561, rev. W. H. C. Frend (London: SPCK, 1989), 35–3Google Scholar

2 Hick, , ‘Jesus and the World Religious’, in Hick, (ed.) The Myth of God Incarnate (London: SCM Press, 1976), 178Google Scholar

3 In an illuminating essay (‘What Does Chalcedon Solve and What Does it Not? Some Reflections on the Status and Meaning of the Chalcedonian Definition’, in Davis, , Kendall, and O'Collins, (eds.) The Incarnation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 143–63CrossRefGoogle Scholar), Sarah Coakley outlines three approaches to an understanding of Chalcedon to be found in the literature, and finding them all wanting in some respect, proposes a fourth. The first interpretation takes the definition to lay down the terms in which the Incarnation is to be described, but makes no ontological claims. A second takes the definition to be metaphorical. Both of these Coakley finds implausible. The third approach is one found in analytic philosophical treatments of the Incarnation, typified by Brown (The Divine Trinity (London: Duckworth, 1985)Google Scholar and Morris (The Logic of God Incarnate (Cornell: Cornell University Press, 1986)Google Scholar. In these, the Chalcedonian statement is taken to be, or intended to be, a literally true description of the Incarnation. Coakley applauds the recognition in this approach that the statement does intend to be truly descriptive of an actual state of affairs, but points out that ‘literal’ has additional connotations that may not appropriately represent the intentions of those who originally constructed the statement. Her own proposal is that Chalcedon, in her words, ‘sets a ‘boundary’ on what can, and cannot, be said, by first ruling out three aberrant interpretations of Christ…second, providing an abstract rule of language for distinguishing duality and unity in Christ [i.e. two natures but one person], and third, presenting a ‘riddle’ of negatives by means of which a greater (though undefined) reality may be intimated'. (Coakley ‘What Does Chalcedon Solve and What Does it Not?’, 161.)

4 The Embodiment of Mind, or What Use is Having a Body?’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 74 (1973–4), 3355Google ScholarPubMed.

5 Swinburne, , The Coherence of Theism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), 103Google Scholar.

6 Dennett, ‘Where Am I?’, in Brainstorms (Harvester Press, 1978), 311–12Google Scholar

7 Hudson, , A Materialist Metaphysics of the Human Person (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2001)Google Scholar; cf. Strawson, P. F., Individuals (London: Methuen, 1959), 116CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, Vol. II (Blackfriars edition) Ia.8.3.

9 The composite view has been articulated and defended both by Eleonore Stump (‘Aquinas’ Metaphysics of the Incarnation’, in Davis, Kendall, and O'Collins (eds.) The Incarnation, 197–218) and by Brian Leftow (‘A Timeless God Incarnate’, in Davis, Kendall, and O'Collins (eds.) The Incarnation, 273–99). Both find the roots of this view in Aquinas.

10 According to St Matthew's narrative:

And he went a little farther, and fell on his face, and prayed, saying O my Father, if it be possible, let this cup pass from me: nevertheless not as I will, but as thou wilt. (26.39)

And about the ninth hour Jesus cried with a loud voice, saying Eli, Eli, lama sabachthani? That is to say, My God, my God, why hast thou forsaken me? (27: 46)

11 See Morris, The Logic of God Incarnate, 103–7; Swinburne, ‘Could God Become Man?’, 64–6; The Christian God, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994)Google ScholarPubMed, ch. 9. cf. Hebblethwaite, Brian, The Incarnation: collected essays in Christology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 31, 68.

12 Whereas I have talked of ‘accounts’ of embodiment, I have followed writers such as David Brown in talking of ‘models’ of Christ's nature. The implication, I take it, is that any theory we come up with concerning the divine must at best be an approximation.

13 Swinburne, , ‘Could God Become Man?’, in Vesey, Godfrey (ed.) The Philosophy in Christianity, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 64–5Google Scholar.

14 Morris, The Logic of God Incarnate, 104–5.

15 Glover, I: The Philosophy and Psychology of Personal Identity (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1989), 1Google Scholar.

16 Perry, ‘The Problem of the Essential Indexical’, Nous, 13 3–21.

17 Gore, , The Incarnation of the Son of God (London: John Murray, 1891)Google Scholar. The kenotic model is defended at length in Brown (The Divine Trinity (London: Duckworth, 1985)Google Scholar). For recent discussion see Peter Forrest's ‘The Incarnation: a philosophical case for kenosis’ (Religious Studies 36 (2000), 127–40Google Scholar), and Evans', Stephen C.Exploring Kenotic Christology: The Self-emptying of God (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006)Google Scholar.

18 Brown, The Divine Trinity, 227.