Skip to main content
Log in

Quine, Putnam, and the ‘Quine–Putnam’ Indispensability Argument

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Much recent discussion in the philosophy of mathematics has concerned the indispensability argument—an argument which aims to establish the existence of abstract mathematical objects through appealing to the role that mathematics plays in empirical science. The indispensability argument is standardly attributed to W. V. Quine and Hilary Putnam. In this paper, I show that this attribution is mistaken. Quine’s argument for the existence of abstract mathematical objects differs from the argument which many philosophers of mathematics ascribe to him. Contrary to appearances, Putnam did not argue for the existence of abstract mathematical objects at all. I close by suggesting that attention to Quine and Putnam’s writings reveals some neglected arguments for platonism which may be superior to the indispensability argument.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. What it is to be abstract has also been a topic of discussion. Perhaps the most popular approach has been to say that an entity is abstract iff it lacks spatio–temporal location and is causally inactive. Nothing I will say here hinges on what abstractness is taken to be; see Hale (1987, chapter 3) and Rosen (2001) for more on the debate.

  2. A few authors differ: Resnik (1997: 45 n. 3) is unsure whether Quine and Putnam intended the argument they are usually credited with; he produces a quotation from Putnam 1971 which he interprets as expressing a different, ‘pragmatic’ argument for platonism (Resnik 1997: 47 n. 7). And see footnote 5 below.

  3. In this exposition of Quine’s ontological method, I have deliberately ignored his theses of ontological relativity and inscrutability of reference. For an explanation of why these doctrines do not undermine the project of ontology, see Hylton (2004), §V.

  4. For versions of this argument, see Quine (1969a: 97–97) and Quine (1981b).

  5. Not every author has agreed with this attribution. During a discussion of Colyvan, Pincock (2004: 67) asserts that Philosophy of Logic is an argument for Harvard realism, not platonism; and whilst surveying the varieties of nominalism found in print, Burgess and Rosen (1997: 201) spend a paragraph arguing for the same interpretation. Since these passages have met with a resounding silence, I judge that a more detailed discussion is required.

  6. The references to Errett Bishop (a prominent intuitionist) and the scorn heaped on the view that numbers and functions are ‘mere fictions’ (74) make this clear.

  7. ‘This [if-thenist view of applied mathematics] is wrong. Cf. chapter 4 [i.e. Putnam 1975] in which it is argued that one cannot consistently be a realist in physics and an if-thenist in mathematics’ (33).

  8. One ‘unconsidered complication’ of my own is that ‘mathematics as modal logic’ changed between 1967b and 1975. In the earlier paper, Putnam uses logical necessity in his modal translations; in the later one, he invokes ‘a strong and uniquely mathematical sense of “possible” and “impossible”’ (1975: 70). Field (1988: 270 n. 36) is baffled by the change, but I think that he himself provides an explanation (at 1984: 85 n. 7): if we use purely logical modality, every consistent theory will come out as equally ‘good’, and, since this is incompatible with bivalence (which the ‘objects picture’ is intended to support), the ‘equivalent descriptions’ thesis will be hard to sustain. Shifting to a less permissive sort of modality resolves the problem. I do not think that admitting Putnam’s change of heart threatens the argument in the text.

  9. In conversation with the author in Sheffield, 2005, Putnam confirmed that his 1971 and 1975 were intended to establish Harvard realism rather than platonism.

  10. Indeed, there are passages where he seems to suggest that ‘mathematics as modal logic’ is superior to the standard picture: ‘The theory of mathematics as the study of special objects has a certain implausibility which, in my view, the theory of mathematics as the study of ordinary objects with the aid of a special concept does not…[P]uzzles… as to how one can refer to mathematical objects… can be clarified with the aid of modal notions’ (1975: 72).

  11. Quine (1960: 242) argues that there is no syntactic criterion of ontological commitment that applies directly to natural language sentences: ‘[A]t best there is no simple correlation between the outward forms of ordinary affirmations and the existences implied’. To show this, Quine points out that the sentence ‘Agnes has fleas’ can be interpreted as ‘∃x (Fx & Gx)’ whereas other sentences of the same form, such as ‘Tabby eats mice’ and ‘Ernest hunts lions’, cannot. (see also Quine 1969a: 106.)

  12. Maddy (1997: 133–143) attacks the conjunction of confirmational holism and Quine’s criterion of ontological commitment. Only recently has she chosen to lay the blame specifically with confirmational holism. For commentary on Sober, see Resnik (1997, chapter 7), Colyvan (2001: 126–134), and Leng (2002). For commentary on Maddy, see Colyvan (2001, chapter 5) and Leng 2002).

References

  • Burgess, J., & Rosen, G. (1997). A subject with no object: Strategies for nominalistic interpretation of mathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D., Manley, D., & Wasserman, R. (Eds.). Metametaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming

  • Colyvan, M. (2001). The indispensability of mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1977). The method of truth in metaphysics. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 2, 244–254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1984). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1980). Science without numbers. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1984). Is mathematical knowledge just logical knowledge? Philosophical Review, 93, 509–552. Reprinted with postscript in Field 1989: 79–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1988). Realism, mathematics and modality. Philosophical Topics, 19, 57–107. Reprinted in Field 1989: 227–281.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1989). Realism, mathematics and modality. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N., & Quine, W. V. (1947). Steps toward a constructive nominalism. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 12, 105–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gross, S. (2004). Putnam, context, and ontology. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 34, 507–554.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B. (1987). Abstract objects. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hellman, G. (1989). Mathematics without numbers. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hellman, G. (1999). Some ins and outs of indispensability: A modal-structural perspective. In A. Cantini et al. (Eds.), Logic and foundations of mathematics (pp. 25–39). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. (1984). Science nominalized. Philosophy of Science, 51, 529–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Timmons, M. (2002). Conceptual relativity and metaphysical realism. Philosophical Issues, 12, 74–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hylton, P. (2004). Quine on reference and ontology. In R. F. Gibson (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Quine (pp. 115–150). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kirk, R. (2004). Indeterminacy of translation. In Roger F. Gibson Jr. (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Quine (pp. 151–180). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Leng, M. (2002). What’s wrong with indispensability? Synthese, 131, 395–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (1990). Realism in mathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (1997). Naturalism in mathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (2005). Three forms of naturalism. In S. Shapiro (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mathematics and logic (pp. 437–459). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Melia, J. (2000). Weaseling away the indispensability argument. Mind, 109, 455–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, A. (1998). Philosophy of language. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver, A. (1999). A few more remarks on logical form. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 99, 247–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (1993). Philosophical naturalism. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2004). A revealing flaw in Colyvan’s indispensability argument. Philosophy of Science, 71, 61–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1967a). The thesis that mathematics is logic. In R. Schoenman (Ed.), Bertrand Russell, Philosopher of the century. London: Allen and Unwin. Reprinted in Putnam 1979: 12–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1967b). Mathematics without foundations. Journal of Philosophy, 64, 5–22. Reprinted in his 1979: 43–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1971). Philosophy of logic. New York: Harper. Reprinted in his 1979: 323–357.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). What is mathematical truth? In Mathematics, matter and method: Philosophical papers (Vol. 1, 2nd. ed., pp. 60–78). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Putnam, H. (1979). Mathematics, matter and method: Philosophical papers (Vol. 1, 2nd. ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Putnam, H. (1990). Rethinking mathematical necessity. In J. Conant (Ed.), Words and life (pp. 245–263). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1996). On Wittgenstein’s philosophy of mathematics. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Suppl. Vol. 70, 243–264.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (2004). Ethics without ontology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1969a). Existence and quantification. L’Âge de la Science, 1, 151–164. Reprinted in Quine 1969b: 91–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1969b). Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1981a). Theories and things. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1981b). Things and their place in theories. Reprinted in Quine 1981a: 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1981c). Responding further to Kripke. Reprinted in Quine 1981a: 174–175.

  • Resnik, M. (1995). Scientific vs. mathematical realism: The indispensability argument. Philosophia Mathematica, 3, 166–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, M. (1997). Mathematics as a science of patterns. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (2001). Abstract objects. In Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2001 Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2001/entries/abstract-objects/.

  • Sainsbury, M. (1991). Logical forms. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (1997). Philosophy of mathematics: Structure and ontology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2001). Four-dimensionalism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. Ontological realism. In D. Chalmers, D. Manley, & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming.

  • Sober, E. (1993). Mathematics and indispensability. Philosophical Review, 102, 35–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szabó, Z. G. (2003). Nominalism. In M. J. Loux & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics (pp. 11–45). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (2002). The number of things. Philosophical Issues, 12, 167–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vineberg, S. (1996). Confirmation and the indispensability of mathematics to science. Philosophy of Science, 63(supplement), S256–S263.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (2000). Apriority and existence. In P. Boghossian & C. Peacocke (Eds.), New essays on the a priori (pp. 197–228). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper draws on chapter 3 of my Ph.D. thesis (Nominalist accounts of Mathematics, University of Sheffield, UK). I would like to give the warmest of thanks to Rosanna Keefe and Chris Hoookway for their painstaking supervision. I would also like to thank Hilary Putnam for discussing his work with me. For comments and advice, thanks to Chris Daly, Michael Scott, and an anonymous referee.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Liggins.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Liggins, D. Quine, Putnam, and the ‘Quine–Putnam’ Indispensability Argument. Erkenn 68, 113–127 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-007-9081-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-007-9081-y

Keywords

Navigation