Skip to main content
Log in

Must realists be skeptics? An Aristotelian reply to a Darwinian Dilemma

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In a series of influential essays, Sharon Street has argued, on the basis of Darwinian considerations, that normative realism leads to skepticism about moral knowledge. I argue that if we begin with the account of moral knowledge provided by Aristotelian naturalism, then we can offer a satisfactory realist response to Street’s argument, and that Aristotelian naturalism can avoid challenges facing other realist responses. I first explain Street’s evolutionary argument and three of the most prominent realist responses, and I identify challenges to each of those responses. I then develop an Aristotelian response to Street. My core claim is this: Given Aristotelian naturalism’s account of moral truth and our knowledge of it, we can accept the influence of evolutionary processes on our moral beliefs, while also providing a principled, non-question-begging reason for thinking that those basic evaluative tendencies that evolution has left us with will push us toward, rather than away from, realist moral truths, so that our reliably getting things right does not require an unexplained and implausible coincidence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a helpful recent overview, see Wielenberg (2016).

  2. Elaborations of Aristotelian naturalism include: Hursthouse (1999), MacIntyre (1999), Foot (2001, 2004), Müller (2004), Thompson (2004, 2008), Hacker-Wright (2009, 2013), Boyle and Lavin (2010), Teichmann (2011), Lott (2012, 2014).

  3. For ease of exposition, I will treat Aristotelian naturalism (AN) as synonymous with Aristotelianism.

  4. For instance, Foot (2001) interprets Nietzsche as accepting the formal framework of natural goodness, while developing a substantive conception of human good that differs from her own.

  5. An exception to this is Setiya (2012), but my appeal to AN is very different from his.

  6. Street sometimes refers to “evaluative realism” rather than normative realism, but I take it that these are same position.

  7. There is a further twist, since a Kantian antirealist denies that an ideally coherent Caligula is possible. But Street’s own view is “Humean antirealism,” and the distinction between Humean and Kantian antirealism will not be crucial to my essay.

  8. See Wielenberg (2010), Brosnan (2011), Skarsaune (2011).

  9. See e.g. Shafer-Landau (2012, 33).

  10. I take this label from Cuneo (2014).

  11. As Street says, “Given the odds we can reasonably suppose to be in play in this ‘normative lottery’ case, we should conclude that in all probability we didn’t win” (Street 2016, 315).

  12. I offer my own analysis of what is wrong with no content in Sect. 5.

  13. It is not enough, Vavova argues, for Street to establish the weaker claim that we have no good reason to think that our beliefs are true.

  14. See Annas (2011) and Hursthouse (2011).

  15. The similarities between skill-knowledge and moral knowledge do not mean that moral virtue is a skill. See Hacker-Wright (2015). On the skill analogy, see Annas (2011).

  16. Or at least it would be a derivative and non-paradigm instance of good action. The claims in this paragraph apply to adult human action, which I take to be “acting well” in the fullest sense.

  17. See Hursthouse (1999) and Russell (2009).

  18. See Foot (2001, 12–13).

  19. See Thompson (2008, part I).

  20. Certain cases might seem to stand in the way of connecting the good of and good for in this way. Isn’t it good for a tiger to be given nutritious food in a zoo, rather than to face the difficult task of hunting as the naturally good tiger does? Wouldn’t it be good for a tiger if it could run 150mph, although that is certainly not required for being good as a tiger? What if a tiger was given the capacity to philosophize or to enjoy literature? Wouldn’t that be good for the tiger, even though such things are clearly not part of the naturally good life-cycle of “the tiger”? For a response to such examples on behalf of AN, see Groll and Lott (2015).

  21. In saying this, we need not suppose that humans first acquire a “blueprint” for living well and then implement that blueprint as the “Grand End” of all their deliberations.

  22. As Michael Thompson says, “Of course we have no way of judging what practical thoughts and what range of upbringings might be characteristic of the human, and sound in a human, except through application of our fundamental practical judgments—judgments about what makes sense and what might count as a reason and so forth.” Thompson (2004, 73). See also Lott (2012).

  23. This is clear in Foot (2001, 2004).

  24. Cf. MacIntyre: “[F]or us human beings it is because we do have reasons for action prior to any reflection, the kinds of reasons that we share with dolphins and chimpanzees, that we have an initial matter for reflection, a starting point for the transition to rationality which a mastery of some of the complexities of language can provide” (1999, 56).

  25. In his response to Street, Enoch (2010) concedes that his view requires a “small miracle.” I thank an anonymous reviewer for Philosophical Studies for pressing me to consider whether Aristotelian naturalism requires a miracle of its own.

  26. See the second epigram to this paper.

  27. AN holds that the normative authority of moral considerations does not derive from an individual’s particular commitments, and indifference or hostility toward morality implies a rational defect. In this respect, AN is different from the “society-centered” moral naturalism of David Copp. See Copp (2007) and Copp (2008). In the context of Street’s argument, this difference is important. It means that AN is not vulnerable to the same rejoinder that Street makes to Copp. Rather, AN is an “uncompromising normative realism” in Street’s sense. See Street (2008).

  28. See the first epigram to this paper.

  29. For elaboration and defense, see Brewer (2009), and Boyle and Lavin (2010).

  30. I owe this phrase to Joshua McBee.

  31. This does not mean that every moral truth is about what will directly benefit the agent. On the contrary, it might well belong to humans to act directly for the benefit of others.

  32. In some of her early essays, Philippa Foot begins by reflecting on moral belief and moral argument, and she observes that the content of moral concepts is systematically related to the good of human beings. Then, noting that not just anything can count as harm and benefit for human beings, she points out that not just anything can count as a moral concept or moral consideration. Rather than begin, as I have done, with an account that stipulates the realm of moral truth as that of human good, Foot works her way toward that idea, by considering moral belief and argument. But with respect to ruling out no content, the upshot is the same.

    For another argument against no content, see Cuneo and Shafer-Landau (2014).

  33. I take this phrase from Street (2008).

  34. For one version of this challenge to AN, see Fitzpatrick (2008). For another statement of the challenge, and a partial response, see Lott (2014).

References

  • Annas, J. (2011). Intelligent virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, M., & Lavin, D. (2010). Goodness and desire. In S. Tenenbaum (Ed.), Desire, practical reason, and the good (pp. 161–201). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, T. (2009). The retrieval of ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brosnan, K. (2011). Do the evolutionary origins of our moral beliefs undermine moral knowledge? Biology and Philosophy, 26, 51–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2007). Morality in a natural world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2008). Darwinian skepticism about moral realism. Philosophical Issues, 18, 186–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cueno, T., & Shafer-Landau, R. (2014). The moral fixed points: New direction for moral nonnaturalism. Philosophical Studies, 171, 399–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cuneo, T. (2014). Dissolving the debunker’s puzzle. Expositions, 8(2), 38–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D. (2010). The epistemological challenge to metanormative realism: How best to understand it, and how to cope with it. Philosophical Studies, 148, 413–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick, W. (2008). Robust ethical realism, non-naturalism, and normativity. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 3, pp. 159–205). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick, W. (2014). Why there is no darwinian dilemma for ethical realism. In M. Bergmann & P. Kain (Eds.), Challenges to moral and religious belief: Disagreement and evolution (pp. 237–255). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fitzpatrick, W. (2015). Debunking evolutionary debunking of ethical realism. Philosophical Studies, 172, 883–904.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (1978). Moral beliefs. Virtues and vices and other essays in moral philosophy (pp. 110–131). Berkeley and Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (2001). Natural goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (2004). Rationality and goodness. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Modern moral philosophy (pp. 1–14). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groll, D., & Lott, M. (2015). Is there a role for ‘human nature’ in debates about human enhancement? Philosophy, 90, 623–651.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacker-Wright, J. (2009). What is natural about Foot’s ethical naturalism? Ratio, 22, 308–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacker-Wright, J. (2013). Human nature, virtue, and rationality. In Julia Peters (Ed.), Aristotelian ethics in contemporary perspective (pp. 83–96). New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker-Wright, J. (2015). Skill, practical wisdom, and ethical naturalism. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 18, 983–993.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (1999). On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (2011). What does the phronimos know? In L. Jost & J. Wuerth (Eds.), Perfecting virtue: New essays on kantian ethics and virtue ethics (pp. 38–57). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lott, M. (2012). Moral virtue as knowledge of human form. Social Theory and Practice, 38, 407–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lott, M. (2014). Why be a good human being? Natural goodness, reason, and the authority of human nature. Philosophia, 42, 761–777.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1999). Dependent rational animals. LaSalle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, A. (2004). Acting well. In Anthony O’Hear (Ed.), Modern moral philosophy (pp. 15–46). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, D. (2009). Practical intelligence and the virtues. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Setiya, K. (2012). Knowing right from wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. (2012). Evolutionary debunking, moral realism and moral knowledge. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 7, 1–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skarsaune, K. (2011). Darwin and moral realism: Survival of the iffiest. Philosophical Studies, 152, 229–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127, 109–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2008). Reply to Copp: Naturalism, realism, and the varieties of normativity worth worrying about. Philosophical Issues, 18, 207–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2009). In defense of future tuesday indifference: Ideally coherent eccentrics and the contingency of what matters. Philosophical Issues, 19, 273–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2010). “What is constructivism in ethics and metaethics? Philosophy Compass, 5(5), 363–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2011). Mind independence without the mystery: why quasi-realists can’t have it both ways. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics (Vol. 6, pp. 1–32). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Street, S. (2016). Objectivity and truth: you’d better rethink it. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics (Vol. 11, pp. 293-333). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Teichmann, R. (2011). Nature, reason, and the good life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M. (2004). Apprehending human form. In Anthony O’Hear (Ed.), Modern moral philosophy (pp. 47–74). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M. (2008). Life and action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vavova, K. (2014). Debunking evolutionary debunking. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics (Vol. 9, pp. 76–101). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wielenberg, E. (2010). On the evolutionary debunking of morality. Ethics, 120, 441–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wielenberg, E. (2016) Ethics and Evolutionary Theory. Analysis, 76 (4), 502–515.

Download references

Acknowledgements

For helpful feedback on earlier versions of this paper, I thank: Anne Baril, Talbot Brewer, Jorge Garcia, Daniel Groll, John Hacker-Wright, Rosalind Hursthouse, Richard Kim, Mark LeBar, Matthew Lockerman, Joshua McBee, Daniel McKaughan, and Roger Teichmann. I am also grateful to audiences at University of Oslo, The Catholic University of America, and University of Virginia.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Micah Lott.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lott, M. Must realists be skeptics? An Aristotelian reply to a Darwinian Dilemma. Philos Stud 175, 71–96 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0856-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0856-y

Keywords

Navigation